Core - The Mind-Body Problem (Long)

DP Barrett - The Mind-Body Problem
The mind is the name we give to the conscious element of a human being, our thoughts, feelings and perceptions. We can question whether other people have minds, for perhaps they are simply mindless automata like robots, but you can be certain that you yourself do have a mind. However, there is still a massive question to answer concerning what precisely the nature of the mind is and how precisely it relates to the physical body, and in particular to the brain. Is the mind the same thing as the brain, and does it die when the body dies, or is the mind something non-physical such as a soul? And just how can the vibrant and colourful world of experience and thought that we call the mind be the same thing as the grey matter that we call the brain?  A surgeon can see your brain and operate on it, but surely he could never see your mind nor cut a dream or thought in half with his scalpel?  This is what we call the Mind-Body Problem: what is the mind and how does it relate to the body, in particular the brain?  Is the mind just brain-activity?  Is it the soul?


Dualism
Dualism, in philosophy of mind, is the view that the mental and the physical, e.g. the mind and the body, are fundamentally different kinds of thing. Though Dualism has an ancient heritage, its modern versions largely owe their existence to Rene Descartes (1596 – 1650) who argued that the mind was a different substance from the body. As the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy puts it: “Descartes was a substance Dualist. He believed that there were two kinds of substance: matter, of which the essential property is that it is spatially extended; and mind, of which the essential property is that it thinks.”[1]

The view that human beings are not simply physical beings, but that they have a non-physical aspect is known as Dualism. Dualists take the view that human beings are composite beings with two parts: a physical body and a non-physical mind. Some might go so far as to say that the mind was none other than the soul and they would contend that the soul can survive the death of the body, thus proving that the mind and the body are separate things. Dualism is the most widespread viewpoint concerning the mind, and it is enshrined within all of the major religions, all of which think of the mind as being something that leaves the body at the point of death, thereafter moving on to some form afterlife such as heaven or reincarnation.

Meanwhile, there are people who deny the existence of a non-physical mind and instead believe that human beings are simply physical beings, and this is called Materialism.  Materialists take the view that the mind is something physical, being composed of material just like the other entities in the world; they may say that the mind is simply the brain, or that the mind is brain activity, and therefore when a person dies their mind ceases to exist. For a Materialist a mental state is simply a brain state, it is electrical and chemical activity in the brain, something which can (or will in the future) be explained through science. Dualists argue that a purely physical being could not have a mind, meaning that something like a robot could never be conscious; meanwhile, from a Materialist perspective human beings are simply complex robots of blood, flesh, and bone.


The mind and the soul
There are many Dualist philosophers who would say that the mind and the soul are one and the same entity simply being described with two different terms. For these philosophers the mind is the soul, it is the very essence of a person and it can survive death. The belief that we have souls is of course a major feature of religion also, in Christianity it is the soul that separates man from animals, and in Hinduism the soul is regarded as actually being a part of Brahman (God) that rests within us. Meanwhile a Materialist would say that the mind and soul were not the same thing, for whilst the mind exists and is one and the same with the brain, the soul does not exist and is a fiction; Gilbert Ryle famously mocked the idea of a soul as being “the ghost in the machine.”[2]

Meanwhile others would say that the mind and soul are not the same thing at all, for example, some people take the view that we have three elements to us: mind, body, and soul. There are good examples of this in numerous works of fiction; consider for example the Harry Potter series by JK Rowling. In these stories the evil wizard Voldemort is able to tear off parts of his soul and encase them in physical objects called horcruxes, the point being that they act as an anchor to this world and make him immortal.[3] Whilst his soul is torn apart his mind remains whole and he is able to think and perceive the world just as well as before. Interestingly he becomes increasingly cold and immoral, which highlights the perception of the soul as being something which is strongly linked to positive emotions and the conscience, the soul as a link to spiritual and moral realities not open to the physical senses. Many religions view the soul as a link to God. Another interesting example can be found in an episode of the Simpsons where Bart sells his soul to Milhous. Bart maintains his ability to think and perceive the world, but begins to lack any enjoyment in life, in particular finding it impossible to laugh; he feels cold and empty.[4] Or again in Philip Pullman’s His Dark Materials trilogy a person is seen as having three parts: mind, body, and spirit. The spirits of characters are manifested outside of themselves as talking animals called daemons; in one part of the story a boy has his daemon separated from him, resulting in him feeling lost and cold, and eventually leading to death from soul shock. Though these works of fiction are not the works of philosophers and scholars, they do none the less allow us to explore the concept of a soul.


Dualism and Monism
Dualism takes the view that there are two fundamental kinds of thing, those which are physical and made of matter and those which are non-physical, such as the mind or soul. Materialism, meanwhile, takes the view that there is only one fundamental kind of thing, physical material, and it therefore can be described as a form of Monism (from the Greek word ‘mono’ meaning ‘single’).  Interestingly, however, there is another monistic path that we can take, and that is to deny the existence of physical matter altogether and argue that everything which exists is non-physical. This was essentially the view of George Berkeley (1685 – 1753) who argued that what fundamentally exists is the mind, and that the things we experience are not physical objects out in a material realm, but rather, are like dreams or ideas in the mind, hence the term Idealism is given to this theory. Though the perspective is interesting and noteworthy it will not be discussed in this article, which will operate under the assumption that a physical world (and a physical body) does indeed exist.


Additional Note: Realism Vs Idealism
Since our perceptions of the world are in our minds there is the possibility that everything we experience is in fact an illusion in our minds, essentially a dream. After all, some people have dreams that are so vivid they honestly believe themselves to be awake and having genuine experiences. Rene Descartes considered the possibility that everything he saw might be just a dream, although in the end he dismissed the idea. Meanwhile George Berkeley came to the conclusion that reality really was a dream in your mind, and that there was no external world. Those who believe a physical world exists outside of the mind are called Realists, whilst those who believe the world is imaginary are called Idealists.


What is the mind?
The first task at hand is to define the mind, something which is not easy to do because there is a great debate as to what we should include and what we should not. Taken in a broad sense the human mind consists of several different elements, such as your perceptions, ideas and imaginings, dreams, memories, emotions, desires, and your thoughts, although this may not be an exhaustive list.

Firstly there are your perceptions of the world which are generated thanks to the many senses such as sight, touch, hearing, taste, smell, balance, thermoception (heat), nociception (pain), and so on; contrary to popular belief, there are far more senses than five! These perceptions of the world are ever changing as new information comes to your senses. It is tempting to think that when you see an object such as a tree you are seeing the tree itself, out there in the world, however, philosophers such as John Locke (1632 – 1704) and many modern scientists attest to the view that actually what you are perceiving is a mental representation, something in your mind. A good analogy is with a photo; with a photo we do not see the object itself, but a representation of it. The eyes are like cameras which pick up light that bounces off the surface of objects in front of us; this information is then transmitted to your brain and then a representation of the object appears in your mind. Essentially, then, what you experience is not the world itself, but a representation of the world, like virtual reality in your mind. Your perceptions of the world are in your mind, much like a dream, which raises the question of whether the external world is really there at all or if life is all just a dream.

Next there is the imagination, which allows us to picture things in our minds, things which may not necessarily exist; using our imagination we can take old ideas learned from experience and play around with them to construct new ideas. We can use our imaginations to help us solve mathematical problems, or think of how to rearrange a room, or even the best way to cheer a friend up. We can imagine what the past was like or what the future might be like, or make up stories to entertain people with.

Dreams may be described as amongst the denizens of the mind, they are similar to perceptions and appear to be creations of the mind based on memories, emotions, imagination, and so on. These vivid imaginings are generally experienced during sleep.

Next there are memories, we can recall things that we have seen in the past and see them again in our minds, even if in a less vivid manner, we can picture what we have seen or remember what a song sounds like and play it back in our minds. Arguably what we are doing here is using our imagination to reconstruct the past, and often people remember inaccurately.

Another aspect of the mind is our emotions and desires; we feel happy or sad, or fearful, or angry; we desire things such as food or the company of others, or the latest mobile phone, or to do well at school, or to help people, or to hurt them. Also, we are averse to some things, desiring to avoid them, for instance we generally want to avoid pain. These mental experiences seem to control how we act, and can highly influence how we interpret what we perceive, for example, we might find a painting beautiful or ugly depending on our mood.

The final aspect of our minds that we should look at is something which many philosophers have viewed as being its most important aspect of all: thought. The term ‘thought’ can be used in a broad sense to include imagining things or picturing them in your mind, but most notably it takes the form of the internal monologue of language where we can put our thoughts and ideas in to words and go through them as if you were explaining them to another person verbally. We are able to reflect on all manners of issues, we can categorise and define things, we can use logic, reflect on our own place within society and history, and we can understand what others think about us and why. Moreover we are able to justify our actions with reasons and principles rather than just act on our moods, impulses, and inclinations.


Additional Note: The problem of Solipsism
According to Dualism something like a robot could not have a mind, it may act like it is thinking and perceiving the world, but such mental experiences are not possible for it. The lights are on but no one is home, nothing is going on ‘upstairs’ so to speak. However, can we really be sure that others have minds?  They may act like they are having thoughts, but is this so?  Could it not be that they have no thoughts, no feelings, no perceptions, but are just mindless physical machines acting like they have minds?  Maybe you personally are the only person with consciousness and are ‘on your own’ (solo).  This is the problem of Solipsism: how can you actually know if others have minds like your own? If you think it is obvious others have minds, then ask this: how do you know that your PC doesn’t have a mind?  If a character in a computer game acts angry, how can you be sure that he isn’t?

According to JS Mill the only way we can conclude that others have minds is through analogy; we see that they have the same physical components as ourselves, and that they act the same way, so we guess that they must have a mind just like us (like effects have like causes, and their actions are like our actions). However, this is still just an educated guess, not a proof of their sentience and consciousness.

How have philosophers defined the mind?
Different philosophers have defined the mind in different ways, including and excluding different elements from the above list. Plato (424 – 348 BCE) suggests that perceptions, emotions and desires are parts of the irrational body, but that thinking and imagination are parts of the rational mind, something only found in human beings.[5] This seems to be the line we are taking in common language when we talk about people going out and participating in ‘mindless’ violence because it seems that they are not thinking properly and rationally about what they are doing and the effects it will have, they are just going with the irrational whims and desires, perhaps like animals. For Plato the mind is primarily the intellect, it seeks knowledge and its true home is with the Forms, which in Plato’s philosophy are non-physical eternal truths; the body is like a prison for the mind confining it to the flawed world of the senses and physical things: 

Plato... likens the body to a prison in which the soul is confined. While imprisoned, the mind is compelled to investigate the truth by means of the body... While encumbered by the body, the soul is forced to seek truth via the organs of perception, but this results in an inability to comprehend that which is most real [i.e. the Forms].
Scott Calef, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy [6]

Rene Descartes is possibly the most important philosopher when it comes to the Mind-Body problem and his theory is known as Cartesian Dualism. Descartes took a similar line to Plato when he came to the conclusion that the mind is a ‘thinking substance.’ Descartes attributes sense perceptions to the body and thinks instead of the mind as something that observes these sense perceptions and reacts to them with thoughts. Descartes views animals as mindless automatons, like robots, reacting on instinct to sense perceptions rather than with knowledge or thought; the mind is the intellect and is only present in human beings. Daniel Dennett (who is not a Dualist) explains Descartes’ view using the analogy of a theatre: the mind is like a person sitting before a great screen observing what happens on the screen and reflecting on it. Perceptions and dreams are not part of the mind, but are things it can observe within a ‘Cartesian Theatre.’ The job of the mind is primarily to think and imagine. In his famous book Meditations on First Philosophy Descartes explains his view: “what then am I? A thing that thinks. What is that? A thing that doubts, understands, affirms, denies, is willing, is unwilling, and also imagines and has sensory perceptions.”[7]

Descartes thinks of the mind as being a single indivisible entity, the ‘self’ or ‘I’ which endures and stays the same throughout one’s existence. Whilst the hallmark of physical things is that they are extended in space (having a size and shape and mass); Descartes claims this is not true of the mind which has no size or shape or weight.  Physical things have parts and can be divided, but according to Descartes the mind is ‘simple’ (without parts) and indivisible, as Scott Calef puts it Descartes calls the mind a thing that thinks and not an extended thing. He defines the body as an extended thing and not a thing that thinks.”[8]

Other philosophers, such as David Hume (1711 – 1776), take a much broader view of the mind and would say that perceptions, ideas, memories, and emotions were all equally parts of the mind. Hume rejected the notions of an ‘I’ or ‘self’ instead seeing the mind as simply a bundle of ever changing thoughts with no ‘self’ at the centre of it.  Another thinker of import here is Sigmund Freud (1856 – 1939) who argued that the mind was actually split in to three distinct parts, again rejecting Descartes’ notion that it is a single indivisible unity.


Two arguments for Materialism / against Dualism
In modern philosophy Materialism is the generally accepted view, although it is not without its problems and critics. I will begin this section with two of the most powerful arguments in favour of Materialism because these will help to fully explain the Materialist position and account for its current popularity. After this I will explain the various arguments for Dualism before returning to some more arguments in favour of Materialism. Arguments on both sides have both strengths and weaknesses and these will be explored.


1) The interaction problem
There is an obvious connection between the body and the mind: first light enters my eyes (physical), and then I see an image of a glass of milk in my mind (mental). Next there is a desire to drink the milk (mental), which is followed by my hand reaching out and grasping the glass (physical). Next the milk enters my mouth (physical) and then I experience the taste in my mind (mental). The fact is that physical events result in mental events, and that mental events result in physical events; stubbing your toe results in pain and feelings of annoyance, and thinking of a great idea results in picking up a pen and writing. There is a clear interaction between the mental and the physical, yet Dualism seems to make it totally unclear how this interaction can happen.

It is a principle of science that all physical events must have physical causes. If the mind is physical then what we have is a case of physical processes causing other physical processes, much in the same way as one domino falling causes another to fall by hitting it, or the way one snooker ball impacting on another will transfer the motion. In these cases the cause and the effect have something in common, a similar nature which allows them to interact. But how precisely can a non-physical entity such as the mind cause physical events? How is it that by exercising willpower in the mind I am able to make my hand move and draw a picture? To consider how odd this really is, pick an item you can see that is out of reach, such as a book on a shelf. Now concentrate really hard and try to will it to move with your mind. You’ll find that it is not possible to levitate the item remotely, and many of us would instantly rule it out as impossible, it seems to call for some kind of odd magical power. And yet, somehow we are accepting that the non-physical mind can exercise exactly the same form of control over the physical body, mysteriously making it move by willpower alone. This defies any explanation.

Descartes believed that the pineal gland in the brain was the mind’s method of interacting with the body; the mind controls the pineal gland and then the pineal gland sends out signals to control the body. Descartes chose the pineal gland because it is in the centre of the brain and is a single entity seemingly without parts, like the mind is meant to be. But there is still no explanation of how the mind causes chemical activity in the pineal gland. 

In short, it seems obvious that the mind and the body interact, but it seems impossible that a physical thing could affect a non-physical thing and vice versa, therefore Dualism should be rejected as it makes interaction (which clearly happens) impossible, or at the least it leaves interaction unexplained as we can have no idea how interaction functions. If Dualism is true then interaction is a mystery. Therefore, arguably, we should conclude that the mind and body have the same nature, they are both physical, thereby allowing interaction to be explained.

Some Dualists have turned to the power of God in order to explain this seeming interaction, for example arguing that the body and the mind interact through God’s will; this is called Occasionalism. Alternatively there is the view that physical events and mental events do not actually share a causal link, but just so happen to occur at the same time, so that body and mind are not connected but are side by side; this is called Parallelism. These possibilities will not be discussed here since they rest on divine power, which cannot be proven or disproven.[9]


2) The localisation of brain parts which correspond to mind parts
Perhaps the strongest argument for the mind having a physical nature is that we can make correlations between thought and brain activity as measured by MRI scans. When we think of different things different parts of our brain become active, for example the centres associated with language and problem solving are in the left side of the brain. Complexes such as psychopathy, schizophrenia, addiction, and depression can be related to specific brain abnormalities. Though neuroscience is not yet fully developed, brain scans can tell us a lot about a person, for example, moral centres in the brain have been discovered in the orbital cortex and amygdala which are related to impulsivity and emotions; those with little or no brain activity in these areas characteristically lack empathy, are selfish, and are often immoral, many even becoming serial killers.[10] Steven Pinker is a Materialist and he argues that modern neuroscience has ‘exorcised the ghost’ of Dualism:

When a surgeon sends an electrical current into the brain, the person can have a vivid, lifelike experience. When chemicals seep into the brain, they can alter the person's perception, mood, personality and reasoning. When a patch of brain tissue dies, a part of the mind can disappear: a neurological patient may lose the ability to name tools, recognise faces, anticipate the outcome of his behaviour, empathise with others, or keep in mind a region of space or of his own body...  Every emotion and thought gives off physical signals, and the new technologies for detecting them are so accurate that they can literally read a person's mind and tell a cognitive neuroscientist whether the person is imagining a face or a place...

The first hint came from Phineas Gage, the nineteenth century railroad worker familiar to generations of psychology students. Gage was using a yard long spike to tamp explosive powder into a hole in a rock when a spark ignited the powder and sent the spike into his cheekbone, through his brain, and out the top of his skull. Phineas survived with his perception, memory, language and motor functions intact. But in the famous understatement of a co-worker, “Gage was no longer Gage.” A piece of iron had literally turned him into a different person, from courteous, responsible, and ambitious to rude, unreliable and shiftless. It did this by impaling his ventromedial prefrontal cortex, the region of the brain above the eyes now known to be involved in reasoning about other people. Together with other areas of the prefrontal lobes and the limbic system (the seat of the emotions), it anticipates the consequences of one's actions and selects behaviours consonant with one's goals.
Steven Pinker, The Blank Slate [11]

It seems that our thoughts are dependent on brain activity, that just as digestion is dependent upon the stomach, so too is thought dependent on the brain. The simplest explanation is that the mind is a physical entity, and that when the brain stops working the mind also ceases to exist; why do we need to posit a non-physical entity to do our thinking for us when the physical brain can do the job?  Dualist philosophers are not unaware that thoughts and feelings are often associated with brain activity, but they do deny that thoughts and brain activity are the same thing, for example, excitement or fear will be accompanied by adrenaline in the brain, but a Dualist would say that adrenaline is not itself excitement, adrenaline is a physical chemical whilst excitement is a feeling; you can put adrenaline in a test tube, but you cannot do the same for excitement.


Arguments for Dualism / against Materialism
There are many arguments in favour of Dualism, though none of them are without their problems and it is not possible to include every argument here. Descartes provides two very strong arguments to the effect that the mind has different properties from physical things, and therefore it cannot be a physical entity.


1) The body can be doubted, but not the mind
Descartes wished to determine which things could be known with certainty and which could be doubted, so he set about trying to doubt everything that he could. He found that he could doubt many of the findings of science because sometimes observations can be mistaken, but that he could not doubt a priori knowledge such as geometry and maths, for example that 2 + 2 = 4 or that a triangle must have three sides. One thing he considered was the possibility that everything he saw with his senses was an illusion or dream, perhaps from some malignant demon playing tricks on his mind. This made it possible that all of the things he had seen and experienced were in fact fabrications; perhaps the other people he saw and the buildings he had visited were just chimeras in a dream. But this then made it possible that even his body was an illusion too. There was only one thing that he could not be made to doubt, and that was that he had a mind and was thinking. Therefore, he concluded that the body and mind were separate things which could exist independently of one another:

I will suppose then, that everything I see is spurious. I will believe that my memory tells me lies, and that none of the things that it reports ever happened. I have no senses. Body, shape, extension, movement and place are chimeras...  Am I not so bound up with a body and with senses that I cannot exist without them? ... No: if I convinced myself of something or thought of anything at all then I certainly existed... I must finally conclude that this proposition, I am, I exist, is necessarily true whenever it is put forward by me or conceived in my mind. But I do not yet have sufficient what this ‘I’ is that now necessarily exists...  Thinking?  At last I have discovered it – thought; this alone is inseparable from me. I am, I exist, that is certain. But for how long? For as long as I am thinking. For it could be that were I totally to cease from thinking, I should totally cease to exist.
Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, Meditation II [12]

This long argument is often summed up with the simple quote “I think therefore I am.” The essence of a human being is their thoughts, without these we cease to exist; the body can be separated from thought because we can imagine the body not being there at all and yet the thoughts continuing. Similarly, we can imagine taking away this specific body (brain and all) and instead placing my thoughts and consciousness in to another body. It just might be that I am an alien with a ball of slime for a body and that I am just dreaming I have arms and legs etc. Since body and mind are conceptually separable they must be different objects entirely, capable of independent existence, thus Descartes concludes “I am really distinct from my body, and can exist without it.”[13]

However, Descartes’ argument is riddled with assumptions which render it ineffective. We know that sight is dependent on the eyes such that if a person’s eyes were removed they would see nothing. Similarly, removing the stomach would take away feelings of hunger, and removing the ears would render a person deaf. Descartes concludes that he is not the same thing as his perceptions etc. and is in some way distinct from them. Here Descartes has a point. But then Descartes asks us to imagine the removal of the whole body, including the brain, and he believes that thought would still remain without it. But a Materialist would reject this and say that without the brain there are no thoughts, so without the brain Descartes’ would no longer exist. Indeed, neuroscientists have removed parts of the brain or seen the effects of brain parts being damaged, and the result is that parts of a person’s consciousness are changed or removed entirely, as Steven Pinker’s comments above explained. Descartes says that he can imagine existing without his body, but he comes from a position of doubt and therefore of ignorance; Lois Lane can imagine Clark Kent dying and Superman continuing to exist, but this is only because she is ignorant of the fact that they are actually one and the same person, in reality if one is removed, so too is the other, and a Materialist would say the same counts for the brain and mind.


2) The mind is not extended in space and is indivisible
Descartes argues that the mind and the body must be different substances because they have entirely different properties; this is why he is called a substance Dualist. To quote Scott Calef, “substance Dualists typically argue that the mind and the body are composed of different substances and that the mind is a thinking thing that lacks the usual attributes of physical objects: size, shape, location, solidity, motion, adherence to the laws of physics, and so on.”[14]  Descartes argues that whilst physical objects have dimensions in space and weight the same does not hold of thoughts, for example, an apple may be 15 cm in circumference and weigh 200 grams, but the same cannot be said of your thoughts of an apple in your mind. As Calef puts it “although it makes sense to speak of the left or right half of the brain, it makes no sense to speak of half of a desire, several pieces of a headache, part of joy, or two-thirds of a belief.”[15] Descartes explains the difference himself thusly:

There is a great difference between the mind and the body, inasmuch as the body is by its very nature always divisible, while the mind is utterly indivisible. For when I consider the mind, or myself in so far as I am merely a thinking thing, I am unable to distinguish any parts within myself; I understand myself to be something quite single and complete.
Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, Meditation VI [16]

We can say that the brain activity related to my desire to eat pizza is 8 cm away from the brain activity related to my thinking about driving my car, but does it make any sense to say that my thoughts of pizza are 8 cm away from my thoughts about my car?  Surely not, surely it seems like these thoughts have no particular spatial relationship to each other whatsoever, they are neither close to each other or far away, they are both just there in the mind; the mind is without shape or dimensions.  If the mind and the brain are the same thing then surely what we say about one must also be true of the other, for example, Cicero and Tully are the same person, so if Cicero was 6 feet tall then the same must be true of Tully, and if Tully was a Roman orator then the same must by true of Cicero; this is called Leibniz’s Law (if x = y, then what is true about x is also true about y). But we can see this does not hold with the brain and mind; statements about the brain are not always true about the mind; the brain and body can be described in terms of dimensions, weight, and so on, and the brain can be divided, but this does not seem to be the case with the mind. Or again, a thought can be true or false, but a brain state cannot be true or false, it just is. The implication is that the mind and the brain cannot be the same thing because what is said about one cannot always be said of the other.

Materialist objection: the mind is divisible
According to Descartes the mind must be different from the body because: (i) unlike the body, thoughts or ‘the mind’ cannot be measured in terms of dimensions such as height, width, volume or weight; (ii) the mind cannot be divided. These properties are essential to physical material, so if Descartes is right then the mind seems not to be physical.

However, it might be argued that the mind is divisible, for example, John Locke pointed out that the stream of consciousness is divided by sleep when we become unconscious; the only link to our past is memory, and memories can be forgotten or in some cases imagined.  Sigmund Freud argued that the mind actually had three parts, one which was conscious, the ‘ego’ (which is equivalent to Descartes’ mind), the other two which are subconscious, the ‘id’ and ‘super-ego.’ The id is a riotous collection of our uncontrolled thoughts and desires, many of which are suppressed because of being socially unacceptable, for example, violent and selfish urges, stressful memories, and sexual urges. Meanwhile, the super-ego is the thoughts that have been forced in to our head by socialisation, it is the moral conscience that battles with and suppresses the id and forces us to think of others. The ego is merely the desktop of the mind, it is the tip of the iceberg, the edited highlights.

Many people disagree with Freud’s psychology, but it can still be quite forcefully argued that the mind is divisible. The mind appears to be composed of a variety of different elements: there are thoughts, perceptions, emotions, memories, imaginings, and dreams, and each of these has its variations, for example we perceive thousands of different things via the senses in any moment, filtering through it subconsciously and picking out the most important details to concentrate on, and these perceptions change constantly, as do our thoughts and emotions. As David Hume puts it, the mind is “nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement.”[17]

Just as the brain has many parts it seems we can argue that the mind also has many parts, and thus it is divisible. This does not necessarily mean that the mind must be physical, perhaps non-physical things have parts too, but it does mean that Descartes’ argument loses some of its force. However, Dualists can still maintain that thoughts and feelings do not have extension or weight, and that this makes the properties of the mind different from those of physical things. In short, perhaps the mind is divisible, but we still cannot attribute dimensions and weight to its parts, so it still does not seem to be a physical thing.

However, Descartes could still argue that the mind is indivisible, because his philosophy does not necessarily say that perceptions and thoughts and feelings are part of the mind itself, rather, Descartes seems to be arguing that the mind is the ‘self’ or ‘I’ which experiences these things. On this interpretation, the essence of a person is the ‘thinking substance’ which observes perceptions, creates thoughts and feelings, and so on. The thoughts and feelings may be various, and they may come and go and change, but the ‘self’ is not, the self is an indivisible thinking substance. Think about the Cartesian Theatre analogy again, the self is not the perceptions on the screen or the noise from the speakers (etc.), it is the man sitting watching these things and reacting to them.

But again this view can be challenged, in particular by David Hume who claimed that there is no such thing as the self. It is not the case that we have a self and then we have the perceptions; when we introspect we find that there is no self, there is no viewer of perceptions or thinker of thoughts, all we ever find is the perceptions themselves and the thoughts themselves. And if we took all the individual perceptions and thoughts away we would not be left with a self or ‘I’ that simply had nothing to think about, there would simply be nothing:

If any impression gives rise to the idea of self, that impression must continue invariably the same, through the whole course of our lives; since self is supposed to exist after that manner. But there is no impression constant and invariable. Pain and pleasure, grief and joy, passions and sensations succeed each other, and never all exist at the same time...  For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe anything but the perception. When my perceptions are removed for any time, as by sound sleep; so long am I insensible of myself, and may truly be said not to exist. And were all my perceptions removed by death, and could I neither think, nor feel, nor see, nor love, nor hate after the dissolution of my body, I should be entirely annihilated...  I may venture to affirm of the rest of mankind, that they are nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement.
David Hume, A Treatise on Human Nature, Of Personal Identity [18]

Hume states that there is no ‘I’ or ‘self’ which perceives things, there are only the perceptions themselves. We do not ever catch sight of some ‘self’ or ‘thinking substance’ which generates thoughts and ideas, thoughts just appear. When we subtract all the contents of the mind, such as specific thoughts, perceptions, and feelings we are not left with a bare ‘self’ or some ‘thinking substance’ but instead we are left with nothing, a void. This is what a dreamless sleep is like, and this is what Hume supposes that death is like. Hume concludes that there is no indivisible ‘I’ or ‘self’ at the centre of our minds, the mind is just a collection or ‘bundle’ of changing thoughts and perceptions; this is now known as the ‘bundle’ theory of mind.

Again, if the mind is divisible it takes a lot of the strength out of Descartes’ Dualist argument, but it still might be the case that this mind ‘bundle’ composed of many elements is non-physical. Hume’s thesis actually bears a resemblance to the Buddhist theory of mind, anatman (meaning ‘no self’). Buddhists deny that there is a changeless soul, and instead see the mind as a changing set of desires and thoughts; these thoughts are non-physical and can be reborn in to a new body, but over a lifetime the whole composition of the mind changes so that between childhood and adulthood, and even day to day, nothing remains quite the same. None the less, for Buddhists the mind is still non-physical, it is just changeable.

The Cartesian notion of a single indivisible consciousness has also been challenged by brain science.  In certain cases of epilepsy it is necessary to cut the corpus callosum, the part of the brain which links the two hemispheres. Experiments on people with a ‘split brain’ by scientists such as Michael Gazzaniga have actively demonstrated that consciousness can be split so that one part of a person is aware of things, whilst another part is not.  The right side of each eye’s field of vision is wired in to the left brain, and the left side of each eye’s field of vision is wired in to the right brain. If we show a picture to the left field of vision the right brain becomes aware of it, but the person is unable to name what he sees because the brain’s language centres are in the left brain. Some of these experiments show direct evidence that one part of you can be aware of things that the other part is not, and thus that the self can be split, as Brain King explains:

In the experiment each hemisphere of a patient was exclusively presented a picture, one of a snow scene and one of a chicken’s foot; the patient was also shown (to both hemispheres) four picture cards.  The right hemisphere saw the picture on the left (the snow scene), and the left hemisphere saw the picture on the right (the chicken foot).  Both hemispheres could see all [four] of the cards. They were asked to select a card that would fit the picture and the left hand pointed to the right hemisphere’s choice (a shovel) and the right hand pointed to the left hemisphere’s choice. The patient was then asked why his left hand had had chosen the shovel; but the left hemisphere which deals in words, listens to language and interprets it and talks, did not know why the right hand hemisphere had chosen the shovel as it had not seen the snow scene. So the left hemisphere made up a story and claimed that it selected the shovel to clean out a chicken shed.
Brian King, Arguing About Philosophy

In this example, the left brain did not know why the right brain had selected the shovel, demonstrating that consciousness had been split, so it is as if we have a left-self and a right-self. Not only that, but the left brain lies, it does not just say “I don’t know”, which is the actual answer, it invents a reason. This seems to indicate that when we act we often do so on some kind of impulse, and that our reasons and justifications are invented after the event, which has implications in terms of freewill, and might also suggest that our thought processes aren’t really controlling us, they are often something fabricated by the brain somehow; a worrying thought for one such as Descartes who believed thought to be the very crux of the mind! It seems that we must conclude against Descartes’ view that the self is indivisible, and the evidence given strongly indicates that the mind is heavily dependent on the brain. However, it is not impossible that the mind is non-physical, for example, epiphenomenalism (discussed below) takes the view that the mind is non-physical, but that it is generated by brain activity and dies when the brain stops working.


Arguments for Dualism continued…
The arguments so far prevented seem to suggest that Materialism has the upper hand because it has the weight of science on its side in the form of neuroscience and brain scans, and also because both of Descartes’ arguments have flaws. However, there are many other arguments for Dualism which may be granted some strength and are worthy of consideration.


3) If Materialism is correct then we are just biological robots
According to Materialism human beings are essentially complex arrangements of atoms, and our brains are like complex organic computers. But if this is the case then it follows that it should be theoretically possible to create a robot or computer that is self-aware just like a human being is, a computer which can see, hear, experience emotions, think for itself and so on, just like we do. Many people do not see how this is possible, and therefore reject the possibility that we are just biological robots.

Consider a watermill; it is a machine made from wood, stone, and metal. Water is poured on a wheel with cogs which then turns, communicating its motion down a shaft. This shaft turns further cogs which transmit the circular motion to a pair of stones which grind up grain. The idea that a watermill made of such materials could feel and think seems laughable, how could it ever feel the coldness of the water coming in, or have knowledge of its purpose, or feel indigestion when grain gets stuck in its millstones?  Now think of a computer’s microchips, surely these are little different from the watermill, they’re just smaller. Electric pulses enter the microchip, these then set off a complex system of switches which are either on or off (this is how binary code works, 0 = off, 1 = on), eventually resulting in various beads of light on the computer screen being activated to generate images. The idea that the computer knows what it is doing, for example that it understands Pythagoras’ theorem or sees the image it has just found on Google, seems every bits as unbelievable as the idea of a millstone feeling indigestion. It seems impossible to understand how a physical thing made of atoms, such as a microchip could produce consciousness, and seemingly the same applies to the human brain; an individual cell can’t be conscious, so how is it that a grouping of cells suddenly produces perceptions and emotions and thoughts and awareness?  As Jerry Fodor puts it “Nobody has the slightest idea how anything material could be conscious. Nobody even knows what it would be like to have the slightest idea about how anything material could be conscious.”[19]  It seems impossible that microchips could be conscious, so conscious robots seems to be an impossibility, but similarly it also seems impossible that the neurons which make up the brain could be conscious, so how can the mind be physical?

To see the problem, consider what brain activity is. Electrical activity in one neuron causes that neuron to discharge a certain chemical – called a neurotransmitter – which seeps out to another neuron across what is known as a synaptic gap, which causes the second neuron to fire, and so on. That, ultimately, is what brain activity is. But how can this sort of thing add up to the feeling you get when, say, you stub your little toe, or fall in love, or see your favourite team win? Brain activity, that is, just seems the wrong sort of thing to add up to consciousness.
Mark Rowlands, The Philosopher at The End of The Universe [20]  

However sophisticated, a machine is still just a machine, and a mere machine cannot see, or taste, or feel pain or anger, or fall in love. It may perform all sorts of actions, but there is nothing going on ‘inside.’
Chris Horner and Emrys Westacott, Thinking Through Philosophy [21]

On the other hand, Materialists say that robots could potentially have minds, and that human beings are indeed robots, it is just that we are extremely complex, as Pinker puts it “the brain has a staggering complexity – a hundred billion neurons interconnected by a hundred trillion synapses – which is fully commensurate with the staggering complexity of thought and behaviour.”[22]  It may well be true that mere atoms cannot have thoughts or feelings, but when we arrange things differently their properties and qualities change, as for example carbon can be arranged as graphite (which is black and brittle) or as diamond (which is clear and strong). Silicone cannot do mathematics, but if we arrange it in to computer chips then it can. Perhaps consciousness is an emergent property which comes in to being when materials are arranged in the correct way; perhaps it is simply the case that our current computers and robots are not complex enough yet?

Mark Rowlands points out that traditional computers are only good for one thing – crunching numbers and symbols to produce a specific outcome. He uses the example of Deep Blue, a computer so ‘intelligent’ that it was able to defeat the great Gary Kasparov at chess. The problem with these computers, which Rowlands nicknames ‘nerds’, is that they are very good at only one thing and awful at anything else, including tasks that we would view as simple such as walking across a room and picking up a cup of tea. All they can do is follow orders written by human programmers, and real life is so complex that we would never be able to create complex enough algorithms for a robot with such a linear computer as its ‘brain’ to deal with even the simplest tasks. For a traditional computer such as a PC to work out how to move a robotic body and balance it correctly in order to walk up a small flight of steps requires millions of calculations.

However, computer scientists have been highly successful in creating what Rowlands dubs ‘computer jocks’ – computers with a ‘neural network’ set up in a way similar to an organic brain. It turns out that these computers are very similar to humans in their abilities – they are bad at crunching numbers and symbols, but they are good at recognising patterns, and this allows them to recognise faces, classify objects, and even converse with human beings to some degree. When placed within a robotic body these computers are able perform actions such as walking up stairs with relative ease, and these robots can even learn by example, for example, the robot Asimo can differentiate between chairs and tables with a high degree of accuracy, even when presented with unusual styles of these items. Rowlands explains “These sorts of task all come down to one type of basic operation: pattern mapping. Recognising a face, for example, involves mapping a current pattern of visual stimulation on to a stored pattern, and using the degree of match up to determine whether the current pattern is the same as the stored one. Human brains and neural network models are, when all’s said and done, pattern-mapping devices.”[23] If we are able to create robots who can act as we do, argues Rowlands, then it should be testament to the view that minds can be generated in purely physical terms, without the need for any kind of non-physical mind or soul.

On the other hand, the fact that a machine might be able to act like a human being is not a certain proof that it actually has a mind like a human being. For example, we might watch two people on a park bench together and see that they are holding hands, laughing, staring longingly in to each other’s eyes, and so on, and we might assume that they are in love. What we are doing here is inferring an internal and hidden mental feeling to the people based on their external observable actions. But what if one of them (or both) is pretending, and no such feeling is really inside them?  We can take this further and ask, what if there’s nothing going on in there at all? Solipsism is the philosophical idea that you personally are the only person with a mind, whilst others are blank and mindless, seeming as if they have feelings and thoughts, but actually not having them at all. The human body completes all sorts of operations, such as making your heart beat or releasing chemicals to control digestion, and yet you have no awareness of these things happening at all, they happen blindly. Why could it not be that all of a person’s actions are like this – robotic and without awareness? Perhaps computers would be like this – able to move and react to the world, but without any mental phenomena occurring at all. After all, we don’t suppose that a speed camera sees the cars it takes photographs of.

Alan Turing (1912 – 1954) proposed a test to see whether a computer was intelligent or not: a person communicates via messages with an unknown other; if the person cannot tell whether he is talking to a computer or not then we can say that the computer is as intelligent as a human being. The basic principle here is “if it walks like a duck and quacks like a duck, then it’s a duck.” In other words, if it can converse as a human does then it must consciously understand as a human does. However, John Searle rejected this, pointing out that that we cannot guarantee that the computer actually has genuine intelligence and understanding rather than just being a mindless machine for shifting symbols. Imagine that someone who speaks only English is sat in a room. At one end of the room is a letter hatch, through which questions are posted, but these questions are written in Chinese. The man cannot speak Chinese and does not understand the symbols, however, he has a very very large manual to look in which shows him explains to him in English which symbols to draw in response to the symbols on the paper posted in to him. He draws these symbols out and passes them back through the hatch. Surely anyone outside of the room would believe that the man inside the Chinese Room understood and could speak Chinese, but we can see this is not so, he is merely mimicking understanding. Similarly, the fact that a computer might be able to hold a conversation with a human does not prove it has a conscious mind, a genuine artificial intelligence, because it might just be mimicking understanding by following symbols rather than understanding anything. Therefore, the Turing test cannot show us whether a computer or robot actually has consciousness.

For a Dualist the very possibility that a purely physical being like a robot or computer could be self-conscious is impossible, as consciousness is only possible through having a non-physical mind, which a computer or robot cannot have. However, for a Materialist it must be possible, at least in principle, to create conscious machines. However, the discussion above shows us that even if a robot were to act like a human and converse with us, this would not prove that it was actually conscious because the computer could be mimicking understanding. Technically we have the same problem with other human beings, we have no certain way of knowing whether they are conscious too (this is the problem of solipsism). On the other hand, it might be argued that robots have to be conscious in order to do the things that they already do, for example, how could a robot like Asimo possibly identify, categorise, and interact with objects without actually seeing them?


4) Dualism is required for freewill
According to Materialism each human being is entirely composed of physical matter. Science tells us that all physical matter is controlled by strict laws of cause and effect, for example, snooker balls do not choose where they end up but simply go where they are directed by forces of motion. If humans are simply physical beings then it seems that we too will be determined by strict laws of cause and effect, for example, that human actions are determined by electro-chemical brain activity.  The implication is that there can be no freewill: human beings are not capable of choosing between different possible actions and different possible futures, but rather, a single specific outcome is determined by chemicals in the brain. It follows, therefore, that Materialism is incompatible with freewill. The only possible way that human beings could be immune to the causal laws of physics, and so possess freewill, is for us to have some part of us which is non-physical, and so free from physical determinism.

Whether freewill exists or not is something we cannot hope to answer here, but it can be argued that this is a weak argument for Dualism because it relies on circular reasoning: this is when we use A to prove that B is true, but we have to use B to prove that A is true, and so we argue in a circle; this proves neither A nor B, but leaves both as unproven assumptions.  In this case we would be presuming that freewill exists in order to prove that the mind is non-physical, but at the same time we need to presume that the mind is non-physical to prove that freewill exists. Before we can use freewill as evidence for the existence of a non-physical mind we must first possess strong evidence for the existence of freewill itself.

Moreover, the argument depends on a logical fallacy; it states that since physical things are governed by deterministic laws, non-physical things must be free from deterministic laws. This is faulty reasoning, it is like saying “girls are governed by human nature, boys are not girls, therefore, boys are not governed by human nature.” It makes sense to say that non-physical things are not controlled by physical laws, but there is still the possibility that they are governed by some other set of laws, so Dualism does not guarantee the possibility of freewill anyway.


5) Dualism is required for an afterlife
According to Materialism a person is simply a complex collection of atoms, and when we die it is because we, as machines, are irreparably damaged; consciousness stops when the brain stops working and after death the body simply decays. It seems that Dualism is required in order for there to be the possibility of life after death as this is the only way the mind could survive the dissolution of the physical body. If we can prove that there is an afterlife, then this will be strong evidence that the mind is non-physical; although we like the idea of there being an afterlife, we cannot simply presume the afterlife and soul are real, we need evidence first, otherwise we are again arguing in a circle.

Evidence for the existence of an afterlife does exist, but its strength is often questioned. Religious people may offer their religious texts as evidence of an afterlife, for example the Bible states “many of them that sleep in the dust of the earth shall awake, some to everlasting life, and some to shame and everlasting contempt.” (Daniel 12:2). Mediums claim that they are able to commune with the spirits of the dead during séances and deliver messages to the living from their lost loved ones, and there are numerous claimed sightings of ghosts. Some people claim to have memories of their past lives, which appears to indicate reincarnation, and there are several examples of children who have reported stories of previous lives, and have even been able to demonstrate knowledge and skills beyond the ken of ordinary children. For example there is the case of James Leininger who, from a young age, was able to speak of his memories of being a World War II fighter pilot; not only did he accurately describe some of the actions of a pilot called James Houston Jr., but he  was also aware of technical information about second world war planes. His parents claim he had no way of knowing these details, and therefore that his memories must be genuine rather than made up. Lastly there are numerous reports of people having Near Death Experiences (NDEs), in which they experienced travelling down a tunnel of light, or even meeting religious figures or dead relatives, before being rescued from the clutches of death. The extent to which these pieces of evidence can be called reliable or compelling is questioned by many philosophers, who take a sceptical approach to such claims. For example, many scientists believe that NDEs do not demonstrate the existence of any genuine afterlife, but instead show that the human brain is susceptible to hallucinations when starved of oxygen, as is often the case when close to death. Similar doubts can be raised about the other forms of evidence given, which makes the argument from an afterlife dubious as strong evidence for the existence of a non-physical mind or soul.


6) Materialism cannot account for Qualia
According to Materialism we are biological robots, and this implies that we ought to be able to actually make robots with consciousness like our own. Imagine that I were to create a robot, and that the robot had pressure sensors on its metal skin. One day the metal on its skin gets damaged in some way. The robot’s CPU analyses the data from the pressure sensors and registers a change which indicates damage. The robot travels to a local repair centre and has the damaged metal skin repaired. In a sense what the robot has done is not too much different from what happens to injured human beings, we have nerves which detect damage, then once we detect the damage we might go to a hospital to get the problem sorted out, for example having wound stitched up. According to a school of Materialism called Functionalism the robot has exhibited that it has a mind because it has performed the same functions that a mind does, e.g. registering the circumstances and taking the appropriate actions. But surely something is missing from this account of what has happened to the robot: surely the robot has not actually experienced any pain?  Surely the robot will have acted totally mindlessly without any awareness or feelings?

Qualia is the name we give to a raw feeling, such as the taste of wine, the sight of the colour yellow, and the feeling of pain. It seems clear that atoms do not have such experiences, for example a table does not feel pain when it gets chopped in half with a saw. It seems impossible that a mere physical machine like a robot could ever experience qualia, and therefore this indicates that the mind must be non-physical in order to have qualia experiences. The chemical constituents of food and its effects on nutrition are purely physical qualities, but the actual taste of the food is something mental which does not seem to be reducible to physical properties such as chemical formulas. Though I may know all the facts about sugar, such as where it is produced and how, and its chemical formula (e.g. glucose is C6H12O2), none of these facts capture the sensation of its sweetness when eaten.

The idea of qualia derives from the work of Frank Jackson and his ‘what Mary didn’t know’ thought experiment. Suppose that Mary has spent her entire life studying the scientific qualities of the colour red, for example, she knows all about its frequency on the electromagnetic spectrum, and about how the eyes and brain process visual information, and even about its cultural connotations as being the colour of love, or indeed of war and bloodshed. However, Mary has lived in an entirely black and white environment all of her life, wearing monochromatic tinted glasses which effectively make her colour blind. Surely if she were to take the glasses off and step out of her lab and look at some sun ripened tomatoes or a Chinese flag, she would suddenly learn something new: what red actually looks like – something which seemingly cannot be reduced to physical qualities alone.[24]  The conclusion from Jackson is that qualia cannot be explained in purely physical terms and indicates something non-physical in the makeup of the mind.


7) Only Dualism can account for personal identity over time
There is a famous thought experiment called ‘The Ship of Theseus.’ Theseus is the captain of a ship and he is sailing across the seas. Thanks to a variety of accidents, battles, and the general battering of the elements, various parts of the ship get damaged and have to be replaced. First a mast breaks, so the mast and sails must be replaced. Then a fire destroys the deck and this has to be replaced.  Then a storm rips away the rudder and another repair must be made. Over ten years every last rope, sail, timber, and nail of the boat is replaced with new copies, so that none of the original is left. Furthermore, all of the crew have died off or left and been replaced, including the captain, who is now Theseus’ son, Theseus Junior.  How is it possible to say that it is the same boat?[25]

There is a good case to say that it is not the same boat at all, but is a totally new boat, a clone of the old boat perhaps. After all, if I were to give a broom three new heads and two new handles over a number of years we would say it was no longer the same broom, and that the original was long gone, it is not the same object, it is not the same collection of material. But here is the problem: according to Materialism each person is nothing but a collection of atoms, but these change over a person’s lifetime. Old cells die and are replaced by new ones; even your bones are renewed over a period of time. After about 10 years nothing of the original ‘you’ actually remains; the human body is much like the boat. So how then can you be the same person?  Surely common sense tells you that you are now the same person as you were when you were six, but science tells us that the entire body of your six year old self is gone. So seemingly, under Materialism you are not the same person as that six year old ‘you’, but instead you are like a clone of him, a copy with many modifications (e.g. you are now bigger). Imagine, for example, that every year a part of your body was removed and replaced by a synthetic robotic replica; surely there would come a point when we would have to say that you were dead and all that remained was a robot standing in your shoes?

Dualism purports to give us an answer to this riddle: even though the whole physical body has changed, you are the same person because you have the same mind or soul, this being something which does not change but stays the same throughout life. If you are the same person as you were 10, 20 or even 60 years ago, then this does seem to require something that has stayed the same for all that time and has not changed, and the soul seems a good candidate for this. In some religions there is a belief in reincarnation, which means that your soul has come from the body of another person, someone who has died. According to this belief you are the same person as them, even though you have a different body from them, indeed you are the same person even though you may have a different genetic code, personality, race, class, gender, and no memories of that other life.

One suggestion to solve the problem comes from John Locke, who states that you are the same person so long as you remember being your younger self, but this can be countered with examples of amnesia, or indeed false memories. Another suggestion is that you are the same person so long as you have a continuous mental life (including memories), a conception of yourself as being the same person as you used to be. Julian Baggini asks us to imagine being beamed to Mars using a ‘teletransporter’ device.[26] The device scans your body structure, destroys the original, transmits the blueprints to the destination, and reconstructs you from new materials on Mars. You would feel like the same person, and remember being the person who just left Earth, indeed, you would simply feel like you had just fallen asleep in one place and awoken in another. Surely you would be the same person as the one who stepped in to the device on Earth if you felt like you were and could remember being them?  But on the other hand, Baggini considers, wouldn’t it actually be the case that you had just been killed and a clone of you created elsewhere?  Don’t we need the body in order to survive? And yet how can that be true if the body slowly changes?

Derek Parfait discusses the issue of personal identity in depth in his article Reasons and Persons, and provides us with the following interesting thought experiment. Suppose that you could cut a person in half down the middle (let’s call him Derek), and then use some special machine to regenerate the missing halves, ending up with two copies of Derek, each of which had one half of the original. It might be tempting to ask which one is the ‘real’ Derek, but surely each one has an equal claim in that matter. It might be tempting to say that both of them are Derek, or that neither of them is Derek; to a large extent it depends how you personally look at it, so it seems more a matter of opinion than truth. One suggestion is that we should look on them both as ‘continuations’ of Derek: Derek(1) is gone and has been replaced by Derek(2A) and Derek(2B). After all, this is the case with institutions like sports clubs: old members leave and new members come, and the buildings change, but it remains the same club over time because we can see it has a continuing history, with the current organisation having ‘grown out of’ the old institution. Perhaps this is the case with human beings too, over time the old self is eradicated and it is replaced by a new version that is a continuation of the old version rather than being the identical same thing.

The question of personal identity is perplexing because there are so many different options to take for how to solve the problem, so the issue cannot be solved in this short space. Materialism causes a problem for personal identity, because the body changes dramatically over time, so the Dualist notion of a soul that stays the same is appealing. But perhaps we need to accept that there is no enduring personal identity? Just because a possibility is unappealing it does not mean that it is false. However, Materialists are able to provide alternative explanations for personal identity which do not require reference to an enduring and unchanging non-physical mind or soul.


Arguments against Dualism, and for Materialism
Materialism is the position of most philosophers in today’s world, however, there are various different Materialist positions such as Behaviourism and Functionalism. To simplify the debate this article will largely stick to the view that the mind is the brain, or alternatively that the mind is brain activity.


3) The soul / mind is described in purely negative terms
Generally speaking, we come to understand something by describing its qualities in positive terms, for example we may describe a dog by saying that it is a mammal, that dogs characteristically have four legs, hair, snouts with a good sense of smell, and so on. On occasion it may be necessary to use negative terms, for example saying that a blind man cannot see, but positive comments are generally most helpful. However, with the Dualist’s mind or soul we do not find positive descriptions at all, we are simply told that it is not physical, not extended in space, that it is not controlled by the laws of physics, that it is not mortal and so on; at no point are we given any positive indications of what the mind or soul actually is. Though we are told that it is the entity which thinks and feels we are told nothing about how it carries out these processes. We are denied any frame of reference which might help us understand its nature. Mark Rowlands explains this criticism thusly:

The mind has no size or shape; has no mass, hence no weight; has no colour, smell, etc.; is not made up of recognised physical particles such as atoms and molecules; does not obey the laws of nature (such as, for example, the law of energy conservation).

One thing jumps out here of course. This is a purely negative attempt to explain what the mind is. But this is not to tell us anything about what the mind is, it is simply to tell us what the mind is not. It is like trying to explain what a dog is by listing everything that a dog is not: not a rock, not a cat, not a cloud, not a split-level ranch house, etc. Even if you were patient (and immortal) enough to list everything in the universe that a dog is not, you still wouldn’t have gone any way to explaining what a dog is to someone who did not know. And so it is not clear that when the dualist tells us that the mind is a non-physical thing he has said anything meaningful at all. It is not clear, that is, that the dualist has any idea what he is talking about.
Mark Rowlands, The Philosopher at The End of The Universe [27]

The mind or soul is simply a mystery, a ‘je ne sais quoi’ which we are denied any explanation or knowledge of. Effectively then, by referring to a non-physical mind in order to solve problems such as how qualia is possible we are not actually giving a genuine solution, but rather, we are wrapping one mystery for another and pretending that we have an answer.  If this criticism is correct then it could potentially show that the very word ‘soul’ is practically meaningless because essentially no one actually has a clue what they are talking about when they use the word. Then again, the same can be said for various physical concepts; we can explain what atoms are in terms of their sub-atomic particles, such as electrons and protons, and we can explain these in terms of being composed of quarks. What are quarks? They are like condensed particles of energy? What is energy? Can it actually be defined? Many would argue it cannot be, it is an abstract idea that we do not fully comprehend, much like ‘the soul.’


4) The mind is a category mistake
According to Gilbert Ryle (1900 – 1976) the idea of a soul is a category mistake, a mistake that has arisen from confusions in language. We use language to group things and categorise them as being similar and different, however, it is often the case that we make mistakes in doing so. In order to give an indication of what he means by a ‘category mistake’ Ryle uses the example of a university:

A foreigner visiting Oxford or Cambridge for the first time is shown a number of colleges, libraries, playing fields, museums, scientific departments and administrative offices. He then asks ‘But where is the university?’ ... His mistake lay in the innocent assumption that it was correct to speak of Christ Church, the Bodleian Library, the Ashmolean Museum and the University, to speak, that is, as if ‘the University’ stood for an extra member of the same class of which these other units are members. He was mistakenly allocating the University to the same category as that to which the other institutions belong.
Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind [28]

To explain, the foreign tourist has made the mistake of thinking that ‘the University’ refers to a specific building which he has not seen yet, whereas in fact ‘the University’ is a term which refers to the collection of all the other buildings – the libraries, laboratories, dormitories and so forth. He thinks it correct to speak of the colleges, libraries, museums and the University, whereas instead he should realise that the colleges, libraries and museums are the University.

It is tempting to look at your body and say “I can see my legs, and my arms, and my head, and my torso, but where is the me that owns these things?” Because of this we conclude that the ‘me’ or ‘self’ that owns these things is another object separate from them, only one we can’t physically see. Here the same mistake has been made as with the university, thinking that there are the various body parts and then in addition there is the ‘person’ that owns those body parts. Meanwhile, Ryle argues that this is a category mistake – it is not a case of my arms, legs, head, torso and me, but rather, my arms, legs, head and torso are me – ‘me’ is just the word we use for the collection of all these parts.  In short it is not a case of ‘my body and me’ (two things) but rather, ‘my body is me’ (one thing). Thanks to this mistaken way of speaking about ourselves we have managed to double count ourselves thinking that there is the body and then there is a separate self, instead of realising that the body is the self – there is only one thing not two.


5) The idea of a soul is a product of history, when people lacked science
If you have ever seen a dead body, particularly one belonging to someone you knew, you probably found it an extremely odd experience, one that was hard to comprehend.  Every part of the person seems to be there, they still have their heart and lungs and other organs and they weigh the same amount; physically what you see is precisely the same as what was there when the person was alive, and yet, something seems to be gone and missing...  To look upon a corpse it very much seems that something is absent, the personality has gone, and it is all too easy to imagine that some animating force has somehow left the body leaving it motionless. Because of this eerie experience it is easy to think of the mind or the soul as being something that is non-physical and leaves the body at death.

Now, suppose that I were to send an MP3 player back in time to ancient Rome or some similar place. People would probably look at the machine and think that it had some kind of soul with in it that was making it sing, indeed, they might even suppose it to be possessed by a demon. Eventually the batteries would stop working, and surely these ancient people would conclude that the device had ‘died’ and that its soul had moved on to another place. Just as with the dead body it would look the same after it stopped playing music as it had done before, no physical part would be missing, so the assumption would be that something non-physical had left the device, leaving it inactive and dead. But of course we know that this is not the case, the device has no soul, it is simply broken and has stopped working.

The examples of the dead body and the ‘dead’ MP3 player seem to be exactly parallel. Materialist could argue, therefore, that human beings are just machines which unfortunately are liable to break, and that the idea of a soul has come from misunderstanding what happens at the point of death – wrongly assuming that some kind of animating force has left the body, just as would happen with the MP3 player.  If we can give a naturalistic suggestion of how the idea of a soul could have mistakenly emerged then it seems to suggest that the idea is indeed a mistake.


6) Where does the mind or ‘soul’ come from if it is not physical?
When a human being is created it starts out simply as a single egg and a single sperm, things which we would not accredit with minds, consciousness, or souls; it seems clear that sperm and eggs are purely physical objects because they are merely single celled organisms.  When the egg is fertilised by the sperm we again simply have a single celled organism, and yet somehow this grows in to an adult who does have a conscious mind or soul.  It can therefore be asked how this soul comes to be: does the soul somehow grow too?  Is the soul implanted within the growing foetus by God (this view is called ensoulment), and if so, where was this soul before it was placed inside its physical host; did God create it afresh or does he have them stored up for future use?  Horner and Westacott help to explain the various difficulties:

Dualists are going to have to answer some pretty awkward questions in order to make their theory work. When in the development of a human embryo does a mind become attached to the body? How does this happen? Where does the mind come from? Does it ever happen that the mind fails to attach itself? At what point in evolution did minds first appear? How, and why, did this come about? Obviously the list of difficult questions could be extended.
Horner and Westacott, Thinking Through Philosophy [29]

Another question that can be asked is this: if we are machines of flesh and blood and we can somehow have souls, then why could a machine of metal and wires (a robot) not also have a soul within itself, and therefore genuinely have a mind just as a human being does? Also, if amoebas do not have minds, but humans do, then does something in-between like a mouse have a half mind or soul? These questions are perplexing for Dualists, especially those of a non-religious variety who cannot rely on God to plant souls within people. One solution would be to say that the brain somehow generates the soul, so that as the brain develops the soul naturally emerges, but if this is so then it would seem that the soul is dependent on the brain and should stop or die when the brain stops working.


Has Dualism been defeated?
It may seem that Dualism has been defeated and that the idea of a non-physical soul must be rejected; the arguments for Dualism have floundered in various ways, and those for Materialism seem largely to fit in with our modern scientific paradigm. However, Dualism still flourishes in some philosophical circles, particularly in light of the seeming inability of Materialists to explain how atoms can become conscious or experience qualia. For this reason there are philosophers who support a modified version of Dualism called epiphenomenalism.


Epiphenomenalism
Both the Dualist position and the Materialist position have their strengths, but also their weaknesses. Materialism seems to be true because of the correlation between brain activity and our thoughts, but at the same time, arguably it is not clear how mere physical material can allow for qualia and consciousness, it might seem that a non-physical mind is needed for this. Meanwhile, Dualism seems unsatisfactory because of the interaction problem, which is also a threat to the laws of science, according to which physical events must have physical causes.  Epiphenomenalism is an attempt at a compromise between the two positions, although in many ways it seems counter intuitive because it states that “mental states or events are caused by physical states or events in the brain but do not themselves cause anything.”[30]  In other words, that your thoughts, desires, feelings, and even perceptions do not control or influence what your body actually does.

According to Epiphenomenalism the body acts like an automaton, with brain processes governing bodily actions unconsciously, meanwhile, the mind is non-physical and is generated by the processes of the brain like a side effect. The mind does not control or influence the actions of the body, it is merely a spectator. We may feel a desire for an apple and then reach out to pick one up, or we may feel fear and then run away from some kind of danger, but according to epiphenomenonalism these feelings do not cause the actions, they just accompany them. Finally, when the brain dies the mind dies too because there is no brain activity to generate the mind. Consider the following diagram:

Figure A:
Physical stimulus, e.g. light into the eyes.
Which leads to:
Perception of an apple and desire to eat it.
and
Electrical and chemical activity in the brain.
Which leads to:
Action of picking the apple up and eating it.

Figure B:
Physical stimulus, e.g. light into the eyes.
Which leads to:
Electrical and chemical activity in the brain.
Which leads to:
Perception of an apple and desire to eat it.
and
Action of picking the apple up and eating it.

Figue A shows our ordinary conception of the relationship between body and mind: first physical stimulus enters the body, such as light going in to the eyes; next we have electrical and chemical activity in the brain, but also we have mental phenomena such as perceptions of an apple, which may be coupled with desires, such as the desire to eat the apple. Here is where the mind-body problem truly comes from, because we seem to have two things going on and it is not easy to see how they can be related, or how they could both just be the one same thing. Finally these perceptions and brain activity will lead to an action such as picking the apple up and eating it.

With epiphenomenalism, show in Figure B, we have a different series of events: physical stimulus enters the eyes and sets off activity in the brain, and this alone by itself can cause actions such as picking up the apple and eating it – all of which could technically be done unconsciously and mechanically, according to an epiphenomenalist. The primary effect of brain activity is action, but as a secondary effect or side effect, it just so happens that we human beings are conscious – that we are aware of what is happening, that we see and feel and think. But we must not make the mistake of thinking that these mental experiences are actually having any influence on our actions; feeling a desire to eat an apple does not make your reach out and pick it up and eat it, this is just an unnecessary accompaniment to the brain activity that causes the action.

On this theory the interaction problem is half solved: whilst physical events in the brain do cause mental events in the mind, the same does not hold in reverse: the mind does not control our physical actions. An analogy with a steam train is often made. The engine is the brain and it is this mechanical device which causes the train to move; here the motion of the train represents the actions a person may take. Meanwhile, consciousness is like the smoke that rises out of the funnel on the top of the engine, it is a by-product of the mechanical workings of the engine, and though it may accompany the train’s motion, it is clearly not its cause. Just as the steam from the funnel does not cause the train to move, so too the feelings and perceptions we experience in the mind do not cause our actions. When the engine breaks down (here representing death) there is more movement, and there is no more smoke (mind).

A famous proponent of Epiphenomenalism was Thomas Henry Huxley (1825 – 1895), and it was he who first used the steam train analogy. Huxley pointed to the example of a French soldier who had suffered severe brain damage in the Franco-Prussian war as evidence that complex bodily movements could be performed without consciousness, therefore suggesting that mental activity was not necessary for physical actions, all that was needed was brain activity:

If the man happens to be in a place to which he is accustomed, he walks about as usual; [...] He eats, drinks, smokes, walks about, dresses and undresses himself, rises and goes to bed at the accustomed hours. Nevertheless, pins may be run into his body, or strong electric shocks sent through it, without causing the least indication of pain; no odorous substance, pleasant or unpleasant, makes the least impression; he eats and drinks with avidity whatever is offered, and takes asafœtida, or vinegar, or quinine, as readily as water; no noise affects him; and light influences him only under certain conditions.
TH Huxley, On The Hypothesis That Animals Are Automata, and Its History [31]

The evidence suggests, although it does not completely prove, that the injured soldier was unconscious whilst performing these actions and therefore that his actions were controlled by the brain alone without the presence of a mental life. A mental life, therefore, is merely a bonus rather than an essential part of our lives. On the other hand, perhaps we might respond that the man’s consciousness was merely limited or restricted rather than totally absent, for example, perhaps he was able to see his environment and therefore he could dress and smoke, and so on, but the part of his brain relating to pain was damaged so that he did not react to it simply because he did not feel it, much as a deaf person will not react to sounds in the environment around him. However, there are various things our bodies can do without mental awareness, such as digestion, keeping the heart beating, and homeostasis, so it might be asked why action needs conscious thought, especially if we are just repeating patterns of behaviour encoded in our DNA or learned from experience.

Further evidence seems to come from the experiments of Benjamin Libet. Test subjects were asked to press a button when they felt the urge to do so; they should not plan when to press the button or hesitate, but press it as soon as they felt the urge to act. There was on average 0.2 seconds between the test subjects feeling the volition to act and then subsequently pressing the button. At the same time Libet scanned and monitored their brain activity, and it was shown that there was a surge in brain activity in the motor cortex an average of 0.5 seconds before the button was pressed. This seems to show that there is a 0.3 second gap between the brain making the decision to push the button and the person becoming consciously aware of it. This would suggest that it is not our conscious mind which is making decisions, but instead they are made unconsciously without us realising it. Not only does this have implications in terms of freewill and determinism, it seems to show that the conscious mind is indeed an after effect of non-conscious brain activity. It seems that our brain concocts the feeling of having a will that chooses our actions, as Daniel Wenger puts it:

The unique human convenience of conscious thoughts that preview our actions gives us the privilege of feeling we wilfully cause what we do. In fact, unconscious and inscrutable mechanisms create both conscious thought about action and the action, and also produce the sense of will we experience by perceiving the thought as cause of the action.
Daniel Wegner, The Illusion of Conscious Will [32]

Meanwhile, many scientists and philosophers believe that the conclusions from Libet’s tests should not be drawn yet as there are many possibilities and many more experiments to be undertaken. Regardless of the ambiguity of this evidence, Epiphenomenalism seems to be the only option to take so long as we wish to maintain Dualism within a scientific age which sees everything as governed by mechanistic physical laws, as Sven Walter explains:

Epiphenomenalism can be regarded as the inevitable result of the attempt to combine a scientific naturalism with respect to the body with a dualism with respect to the mind. Human beings are exhaustively governed by physical laws so that no non-physical causes must be invoked to explain their behaviour, but since they are also subjects of non-physical minds, these minds must be causally irrelevant. Whenever our trust in the causal authority of the physical is overwhelmed by our first-person experience of ourselves as creatures with an essentially non-physical mind, epiphenomenalism is waiting in the wings.
Sven Walter, Epiphenomenalism [33]


Problems with Epiphenomenalism
There are very few philosophers who agree with Epiphenomenalism, not least because it is decidedly counter intuitive. According to Alec Hyslop Epiphenomenalism is unacceptable because it means that our conscious self – the mind – is merely ‘piggybacking’ on a body which it has no control of, which means that we lose all sense of ourselves. The conscious part of us, the part which seems most important, is in fact an irrelevant addition which makes no difference to the actions of the body that carries it around: “Epiphenomenalism would be the ruin of the self and that self’s life... Our supposed self is illusory, and we are deluded... We lose ourselves when consciousness ceases to be effective in what we chose.”[34]  However, the fact that something is counter intuitive or unpalatable does not mean it is not true.

Another argument is that we experience mental causation, for example, we have a chain of thoughts in our minds, such as the different thoughts you might have whilst trying to come up with a story to write. You draft and redraft it in your mind until you get it right and put pen to paper. Surely it seems that only after we have pictured a possible storyline  in our minds that might we decide to accept or reject it and so write it down or modify it?  Hence our mental life seems to be necessary to decision making and thinking processes, they seem not to be able to be done by the unconscious brain alone. But this again does not prove that Epiphenomenalism is false because according to the Epiphenomenalist the brain is indeed capable of thinking processes by itself, all our mind experiences is a view of what is happening.

Another argument against Epiphenomenalism comes from the evolutionary perspective; all animals seem to be conscious to one extent or another, but if having a conscious mind is unnecessary for performing actions and they can be performed blindly and without consciousness, then we can surely ask why evolution happened to produce creatures that have minds, after all, what practical use would they have?  One possible response would be that sometimes two traits are interlinked, for example, a polar bear can only have a warm fur coat by also happening to have a heavy coat which slows it down, so perhaps similarly it just so happens that the brain set up we need to survive just so happens to produce consciousness, so its existence is just coincidental. The extent to which this is a satisfactory answer is disputed.

Epiphenomenalism, then, is a coherent theory in the logical sense that it does not contradict itself or any other known facts, this means that it might well be true. The central problem in discussing Epiphenomenalism is that the world would seemingly look exactly the same if it were true as it would if it were false, so there is no way of telling whether it is true or not. Many simply reject it because they feel that it is an unnecessary theory and that it is far simpler to just stick with Materialism, after all, Epiphenomenalism offers no real answers to the problem of how consciousness is generated by the brain, it merely states that it is indeed generated by the brain, and that it is non-physical.


Conclusion
The Mind-Body Problem is one of the most famous and difficult philosophical conundrums; the common view of the average people is that of Dualism, and this perspective has been given philosophical grounding by thinkers such as Plato and Descartes, as well as being a central tenet of all the world’s major religions. However, modern science seems to suggest that human beings, like all other life forms, are purely physical beings, and therefore that the mind cannot be a non-physical ‘soul.’ On the other hand, it is argued that Materialism is an empty answer because it does not explain how the non-conscious world of physical material in motion could produce consciousness. But then, does Dualism really offer more answers than Materialism on this score, for here too we find no reason why or how consciousness exists, it just does. A compromise is available in the form of Epiphenomenalism, but it is not clear to what extent this is a viable option either.


Bibliography / References



[1]   Howard Robinson, Dualism, in The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/Dualism/ (accessed 13/09/11).
[2]   Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind, ch.1.
[3]   cf. JK Rowling, Harry Potter and The Half-Blood Prince.
[4]   cf. The Simpsons, Bart Sells His Soul, series 7, episode 4.
[5]   cf. Plato, Phaedo, which discusses Plato’s views on the immortality of the soul.
[6]   Scott Calef, Dualism and Mind, in The Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/Dualism/ (accessed 13/09/11)
[7]   Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, Second Meditation, translated and edited by John Cottingham, p.19, Cambridge University Press (1996)
[8]   Scott Calef, Dualism and Mind, in The Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy
[9]   cf. Scott Calef, Dualism and Mind and Howard Robinson, Dualism for information on occasionalism and parallelism.
[10]  Horizon, Are You Good or Evil?, BBC 2, broadcast Wednesday 7th September 2011.
[11]  Steven Pinker, The Blank Slate, Penguin Books (2003).
[12]  Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, Second Meditation, pp.16 – 18.
[13]  Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, Sixth Meditation, p.54.
[14]  Scott Calef, Dualism and Mind, in The Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy.
[15]  Scott Calef, Dualism and Mind, in The Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy.
[16]  Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, Sixth Meditation, p.59.
[17]  David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, book 1, part 4, section 6, Of Personal Identity:  http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hume/david/h92t/B1.4.6.html (accessed 20/09/11).
[18]  David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, book 1, part 4, section 6, Of Personal Identity
[19]  Jerry Fodor, The Big Idea: Can There Be A Science of The Mind?, in The Times Literary Supplement, July 3rd 1992.
[20]  Mark Rowlands, The Philosopher at The End of The Universe, Ch.3, Terminator I & II and the Mind-Body Problem, p.59.
[21]  Chris Horner and Emrys Westacott, Thinking Through Philosophy,  p.63.
[22]  Steven Pinker, The Blank Slate, Penguin Books (2003).
[23]  Mark Rowlands, The Philosopher at The End of The Universe, Ch.3, Terminator I & II and the Mind-Body Problem, p.81.
[24]  cf. Frank Jackson, Epiphenomenal Qualia, in Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1982),               pp. 127 – 136.
[25]  cf. Julian Baggini, The Pig That Wants To Be Eaten and 99 Other Thought Experiments, No. 11, The Ship Theseus, pp. 31-33.
[26]  cf. Julian Baggini, The Pig That Wants To Be Eaten, No. 2, Beam Me Up..., pp. 4-6.
[27]  Mark Rowlands, The Philosopher at The End of The Universe, Ch.3, Terminator I & II and the Mind-Body Problem, pp. 67-68.
[28]  Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind, pp. 17-18, Penguin Books, (c) 2000.
[29]  Horner and Westacott, Thinking Through Philosophy, p.64.
[30]  Sven Walter, Epiphenomenalism, in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/epipheno/ (accessed 10/11/11).
[31]  TH Huxley, On The Hypothesis That Animals Are Automata, and Its History, quoted in Sven Walter, Epiphenomenalism.
[32]  Daniel Wenger, The Illusion of Conscious Will, quoted in Sven Walter, Epiphenomenalism.
[33]  Sven Walter, Epiphenomenalism.
[34]  Alec Hyslop, Methodological Epiphenomenalism, quoted in Sven Walter, Epiphenomenalism.

No comments:

Post a Comment