Core - Aristotle (Long)

DP Barrett – Aristotle On Human Nature
Aristotle (384 BCE – 322 BCE) was a Greek philosopher and was the student of Plato, however, his philosophy differed greatly from that of his mentor.  To a large degree Plato can be considered to be a Rationalist, someone who seeks knowledge through reasoning, discussion, and contemplation; he believed that truth was discoverable only through knowledge of the Forms which could only be perceived by the mind, and he regarded the physical world of the senses as being in some ways flawed, imperfect, and illusory. Meanwhile Aristotle, the son of a physician, can largely be describes as an Empiricist, someone who attempts to gather knowledge and understanding through systematic use of the senses and observation.  Whilst Plato presents us with dialogues in which we find a discussion, it is in Aristotle that we first find the use of structured and thorough analysis, beginning with discussions about definitions. Aristotle’s surviving works are dictated lecture notes on a wide variety of subjects including:

politics             dreams             biology                        God                 economics

language          medicine          the memory                 physics            psychology

the weather     ethics               metaphysics                 logic                the soul / mind

poetry              knowledge      public speaking           sleep                divination

This chapter will focus on three key concepts in Aristotle’s philosophy, firstly his views on the human soul or ‘psyche’, secondly an explanation of his views on ethics and the meaning of life, and thirdly, his view that human beings are naturally political or social animals.


Aristotle on the ‘soul’
Aristotle’s analysis of human nature is based around observations of human beings and a comparison with plants and animals.  Aristotle divides the human soul in to three parts, but in reality using the word ‘soul’ is deceptive because he is not talking about anything spiritual that lasts forever.  The Greek word that Aristotle used was ‘psyche’ which is better translated as ‘mind’ and is where we get our word ‘psychology’ from.  What Aristotle is actually talking about is the functions and activities that living beings perform, for example, he says that the soul of the eye would be sight, and he adds that when a living being no longer functions it is like a broken machine and it no longer has a soul or mind:

Suppose that the eye were an animal – sight would have been its soul, for sight is the substance or essence of the eye… the eye being merely the matter of seeing; when seeing is removed the eye is no longer an eye, except in name – it is no more a real eye than the eye of a statue or of a painted figure.
Aristotle, De Anima [1]

In modern terms an analogy can be made with a computer: the body is the hardware and the soul is the programmes it is running; when the hardware is broken the programmes stop running and it is ‘dead’; it is effectively no longer a computer because it no longer performs the function of computation. Aristotle begins his analysis by defining life, which he sees in terms of being able to move yourself in some fashion, which includes growth; in order for growth and movement to take place it is necessary for a living being to nourish itself: 

Living… may mean thinking or perception or local movement and rest, or movement in the sense of nutrition, decay and growth. Hence we think of plants also as living, for they are observed to possess in themselves an originative power through which they increase or decrease in all spatial directions; they grow up and down, and everything that grows increases its bulk alike in both directions or indeed in all, and continues to live so long as it can absorb nutriment.
Aristotle, On The Soul [2]

Aristotle points out that all living things, whether they are plants, animals, or human beings, must operate functions which maintain their life; in modern biology we would describe this in terms of the seven life processes such as nutrition, excretion, respiration, reproduction, and growth.  This set of functions he describes as the Vegetative Soul or Nutritive Soul and it is something found in all living beings including plants.  This demonstrates that when Aristotle is talking about the ‘soul’ he is not talking about something spiritual which is only found in human beings; for Aristotle even plants have a ‘soul’ and the ‘soul’ is something which dies with the body when it stops functioning.  With plants, however, this Vegetative Soul is the only function they possess, whilst animals and humans have additional functions:

This power of self-nutrition can be isolated from the other powers mentioned, but not they from it – in mortal beings at least. The fact is obvious in plants; for it is the only psychic power they possess. This is the originative power the possession of which leads us to speak of things as living at all, but it is the possession of sensation that leads us for the first time to speak of living things as animals; for even those beings which possess no power of local movement but do possess the power of sensation we call animals and not merely living things.
Aristotle, On The Soul [3]

Aristotle argues that what separates plants from animals is that animals can experience sensations, which makes them sentient; they have perceptions of their environment. Being able to experience sensations brings with it the ability to experience pleasure and pain, and therefore it creates appetites or desires such as thirst and hunger – animals have appetites for things which give them pleasure and help them to survive, and they have aversions to pain and things that are a threat to them.  Because of these desires the majority of animals have the ability to move (locomotion) in order to attain what they desire and avoid what they are averse to.  What we have here is actually three functions of the soul, the sensory, the appetitive, and the locomotive, but they are closely linked and together are what could be described as the Animal Soul.

The Vegetative and Animal Souls are both found in human beings too, but what humans possess and animals lack is a third and final factor: the Rational Soul – the power of thinking. In part thinking involves imagining things, and animals are also capable of this to some extent as they must imagine what they desire and imagine ways of getting it, but proper thinking is more than this, it involves the reasoning abilities necessary to make judgements, to calculate the best ways of achieving goals and to decide which ends are best and which are not.  Only human beings have ‘logos’ (which translates as both ‘speech’ and ‘reason’), and this gives us the ability to distinguish between what is good and bad:

That perceiving and practical thinking are not identical is therefore obvious; for the former is universal in the animal world, the latter is found in only a small division of it…  Thinking is different from perceiving and is held to be in part imagination, in part judgement.
Aristotle, On The soul [4]

Nature, as we often say, makes nothing in vain, and man is the only animal whom she [nature] has endowed with the gift of speech. And whereas mere voice is but an indication of pleasure or pain, and is therefore found in other animals (for their nature attains to the perception of pleasure and pain and the intimation of them to one another, and no further), the power of speech is intended to set forth the expedient and inexpedient, and therefore likewise the just and the unjust.  
Aristotle, Politics [5]

In summary, then, all living things possess the Vegetative Soul, which sustains life, and this is all that is found in plants. Animals and humans also possess the Animal Soul which is connected to senses, perception, desires and movement. Animals also possess some degree of imagination, however, only human beings possess the Rational Soul which allows for speech, thought, and reasoning and which allows for knowledge, judgement, and argumentation. It is this which makes man different from and higher than the animals.

This may seem very similar to Plato’s distinction between reason and emotions but there are significant differences; firstly, Aristotle is less antagonistic towards the emotions believing that pleasure is an essential part of a good life. The emotions are to be harnessed to help achieve the goals that reason dictates rather than being overcome and controlled; we should aim to feel the right emotions rather than to suppress them, for example, instead of saying that anger is wrong he would say that sometimes it is appropriate and useful, whilst at other times it is not.  Secondly, Aristotle believes that it is impossible to act without a desire, so that appetite would therefore be part of all three parts of Plato’s soul: “if the soul is tripartite appetite will be found in all three parts.”[6]  What Reason does is it tells us which of our desires is most worthy of following, and it reminds us to think about our long term good rather than our short term desires.


Aristotle’s Ethics and The Meaning of Life
Aristotle uses his thesis about the nature of the human soul or ‘psyche’ to support his ethical ideas on what constitutes a good and meaningful human life.  For Aristotle a thing’s function is vitally important and is connected to its purpose; Aristotle thinks that purpose is written in to the nature of things, and that things exist to fulfil purposes and achieve their true nature, for example it is the purpose of an egg to become a chicken, and it is the purpose of a tadpole to become a frog, and it is the purpose of the sun to sustain life on Earth, and it is the purpose of a tree to produce fruit. The tadpole’s only purpose is to become a frog, it is a potential frog which is aiming to become an actual frog. Similarly, Aristotle thinks that human beings ought to develop themselves by taking their potential abilities (e.g. for wisdom and knowledge) and actualising these into genuine talents, thus becoming fully human so to speak. This is a ‘teleological’ perspective on nature, which comes from the Greek word ‘telos’ which means ‘goal’ or ‘end’, and we can see Aristotle’s teleological reasoning when he says things such as “nature, as we often say, makes nothing in vain, and man is the only animal whom she has endowed with the gift of speech.”[7] In making statements like this he is indicating that nature is not blind, but is planned in some way and has tasks or goals to achieve, a perspective that we would generally associate with religion and the view that our world has been constructed purposefully for a reason.  Many philosophers in modern times reject the notion of there being any purpose or goals written in to nature, and instead see things in term of their efficient causes (the preceding events which caused them) and they instead teach that nature is blind and without purpose: nature has not put the sun in place to produce life, the sun just happened to be there and this just happened to allow for life.

None the less, for Aristotle a thing’s purpose is connected to the function it happens to perform, because to be alive is to function, so to live a good life is to function well; here Aristotle is meaning ‘good’ in term of quality rather than ‘good’ in any specifically moral way.  The function (in Greek ‘ergon’) of a pair of scissors is to cut and we can tell the difference between a pair of scissors that cuts well and one that does not.  Similarly, the function of a flautist is to play the flute, and we can tell the difference between a person who plays the flute well and one who does not.  Because we are aware of the function and purpose of a thing we are able to judge how well it fulfils this function, and for Aristotle this is the way we can tell the difference between a good plant and a bad one, and indeed a good animal and a bad one.

A good plant will be healthy and flourishing and it will spread its seed far and wide, and it will be colourful and attractive to the insects it needs to pollinate its species. Essentially we can judge the quality of a plant by how well it functions on a vegetative level, which is the only level it has.  Turning to animals, a good animal is able to get the food it needs to survive, is able to breed well, and so on; a good fish swims well and a good bird flies well; a good bee is able to collect lots of pollen and bring it back to the hive and make honey; a good lion is able to catch antelopes well, whilst a good antelope is able to evade the lions well.  We can judge the quality of an animal by how well it functions on its vegetative level, but also by how well functions in terms of its Animal Soul, i.e. in terms of its sensations, locomotion and achieving its appetites. How keen are the animal’s senses?  How well does it move?  Does it get what it desires, such as food, water, safety, mating, and group dominance?  Moreover, we can see that skills are required for an animal to achieve what it desires, so we can ask questions relating to these skills, is the animal strong, stealthy, cunning, and so on?  These skills are what we call ‘Virtues’ because they are the excellent qualities needed for the animal to have a good well-functioning life (the Greek word for virtue was ‘arête’ which means ‘excellence’).

So now we turn to the function or purpose of mankind.  To function fully and have a good life as a human being is what Aristotle called ‘eudaimonia’ which is often translated as ‘happiness’ but this is a poor translation.  The world ‘eudaimonia’ literally means ‘having good demons (spirits)’ which is to say that the gods are watching over you and ensuring that you are having a lucky and blessed life.  Many modern commentators frame eudaimonia in terms of having a flourishing life or achieving success.  For Aristotle eudaimonia is the natural goal of human beings, but it also happens to be what we all desire, and therefore it is ‘the good’ for human beings:

Every pursuit aims at some good… there is very general agreement; for both the general run of men and people of superior refinement say that it is happiness, and identify living well and doing well with being happy; but with regard to what happiness is they differ, and the many do not give the same account as the wise.
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics [8]      

Aristotle notes that there is disagreement about the nature of eudaimonia, for the common man sees happiness as being a life of pleasure, whilst the ‘wise’ (such as Aristotle) believe it is not.  So what is Aristotle’s conception of a flourishing successful human life?  Firstly a person must be healthy and should have children, which fulfils the Vegetative functions.  Secondly they must have a fair deal of pleasure in their lives and attain the things they desire, a good life should include pleasure, comfort and wealth, things that all or most of us do indeed desire, however, for Aristotle this is not the be-all and end-all of human existence, to crave only pleasure is what he describes as a ‘bovine’ existence, a life fit for animals:

To judge from the lives that men lead, most men, and men of the most vulgar type, seem (not without some ground) to identify the good, or happiness, with pleasure; which is the reason why they love the life of enjoyment… Now the mass of mankind are evidently quite slavish in their tastes, preferring a life suitable to beasts.
Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics [9]

Human beings, alone amongst the animals, possess Reason and knowledge, and therefore, Aristotle concludes that to be a fully functioning human being you must be knowledgeable and intelligent. There are also indications that flourishing human beings should take an interest in artistic creativity and culture. This means that you must aim for something higher than mere pleasure.  This perspective was echoed by JS Mill who made a distinction between what he called ‘higher pleasures’ and ‘lower pleasures.’  Higher pleasures are those which are related to the mind, like science, art, literature, philosophy, politics, and culture; meanwhile, lower pleasures are related to the body such as the taste of food, the warmth of a fire, the idleness of relaxation, and the excitement of sports, gambling, sex, and drunkenness. Mill famously said “it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.”[10]  Imagine a man who has won the lottery and spends his life on holiday, watching sports, and enjoying food and drink; we might say that he has a happy life, but both Mill and Aristotle would say that his life was deficient.  Similarly, someone with a mental disability may be happy, but Mill and Aristotle would say that the person does not have a good or desirable life.  For Mill and Aristotle ignorance is not bliss but quite the opposite, proper human happiness and success has to include cerebral challenges and knowledge; those who can be considered to have lived the best lives are not those who have had the most pleasure, but instead are those who understand their world, especially those who have made scientific discoveries or artistic creations through their hard work.

There is, however, another factor of human existence that Aristotle also took in to consideration when concluding about the true nature of humanity, and that is that we are social beings who are naturally members of a community.  This means that to have a good life must also include good social relations with our fellow citizens, either in the form of friendships or in the form of doing duties to society and receiving honour and respect from our peers; here Aristotle is largely thinking in terms of politics and government, and also defending your nation if necessary, but the conception could be broadened to include numerous social roles such as being a doctor or teacher, and generally serving the needs of others to strengthen the community. However, many philosophers disagree with Aristotle’s perspective here and instead put forward the view that we are not social beings with duties to others, but instead we are individuals whose first and only duty is to ourselves.

So Aristotle provides us with three different possible definitions of what a good life is for human beings: (1) hedonism; (2) a life of duty and citizenship; (3) a life of knowledge and contemplation (in Greek ‘theorea’).  Aristotle rejects hedonism as nothing but a life fit for animals, and he places his own life of theory and contemplation as the highest since only human beings are capable of reasoning and knowledge.  He accepts a life of duty and citizenship as the second best form of eudaimonia, and states that it is the best form of life that many are capable of, since we cannot all be philosophers.  Aristotle believes that these two goals of social duty and knowledge are what constitutes eudaimonia, and they are therefore ‘the good’ for humans, our purpose, our meaning of life. With the goal identified, the next question becomes, how is eudaimonia to be achieved?  This is where the Virtues come in to the equation: various skills are needed in order for you to have a flourishing and successful life.                                               

So in summary, for Aristotle the goal of life is not merely survival or hedonism, it is eudaimonia or ‘flourishing’ and that means to make the best of your potential and function well, and it includes all of the following elements: being healthy; having children; having wealth and pleasure; achieving knowledge and understanding the world around you; artistic creativity and culture; friendship and social duty. The degree to which people achieve this goal is different from person to person, but most people do not achieve eudaimonia to the full extent, none the less, its attainment should still be our goal in life.


The Virtues
In order to achieve eudaimonia certain skills or virtues are required, and Aristotle divides these in to two kinds; firstly there are the Moral Virtues which regulate our emotions, desires, and conduct, and allow us to achieve our goals, for example there is courage, temperance, and charity; secondly there are the Intellectual Virtues which allow us to reason and contemplate well. In many ways having these virtues is itself to function well and thus to be virtuous is itself to have eudaimonia, not just a means to a good life.

The Moral Virtues allow you to control your character and control your actions so that you are a well functioning individual who is capable of doing the right thing at the right time.  Aristotle does not give too many rules about what actions should be done and which should not, because he accepts that different situations require different actions, and he also accepts that different societies have different codes of conduct. By and large doing the right thing involves acting in the way your society expects of you, but none the less there are virtues that any human being will need in order to do well in life.  Temperance is the ability to control your appetite for pleasure; Aristotle believes that it is good to have pleasure in your life, but that too much hedonism means you will not be able to do your social duties or practice reasoning and gain knowledge.  Courage is also a virtue that every person will need, because it is a virtue which regulates confidence; too little confidence and you will not be able to carry out important tasks such as fighting in a battle, or standing in front of a crowd and speaking too them, or reporting a crime to the police; too much confidence and your actions will be foolish and reckless, which can lead to disaster. All of the Moral Virtues exist within a balance, they are a mean between vices of deficiency and excess:


Sphere of action
Deficiency (Vice)
Mean (Virtue)
Excess (Vice)
Fear & confidence
Cowardice
Courage
Rashness
Pleasure & pain
Insensibility
Temperance
Licentiousness
Anger
Lack of spirit
Patience
Irascibility               (too quick to anger)
Self-expression
Understatement
Truthfulness
Boastfulness
Conversation
Boorishness      (being dull)
Wittiness               (being entertaining)
Buffoonery          (being a fool)
Social conduct
Cantankerousness (being unhelpful)
Friendliness
Obsequiousness      (too eager to please)
Shame
Shamelessness
Modesty
Shyness
Indignation
Malicious enjoyment         
Righteous indignation
Envy                    
Getting and spending (minor)
Illiberality (meanness)
Liberality     (generosity)
Prodigality (wastefulness)
Getting and spending (major)
Pettiness           (being small)
Magnificence        (being large)
Vulgarity        (showing off)
Honour and dishonour (major)
Pusillanimity   (timidity)
Magnanimity         (being forgiving)
Vanity (vindictiveness)
Honour and dishonour (minor)
Unambitiousness
Proper ambition
Ambition


The range of Moral Virtues is broad, and it demonstrates that Aristotle is not just concerned with moral goodness, but having a good life in general as well as looking good to others, because he views being generous and witty as a virtues; it is important to be humorous and entertaining, this will help you to do well in life and to be liked by others, but again being witty is a mean which lies between been dull on one hand and acting the fool all the time on the other.  Having the virtues allows you to see when actions are appropriate, it is not about being slightly moderately funny all of the time, but about knowing when to tell jokes and when to be serious and businesslike. Aristotle states that you cannot set definite rules for how to act in every situation, it is a balancing act that takes skill and practice, like learning to use the pedals in a car. The best thing you can do is find people who are regarded as wise and virtuous and copy what they do. Moral excellence comes from practicing and training, so virtue is acquired by making good deeds and self control a habit, as Will Durrant puts it “we are what we repeatedly do. Excellence, then, is not an act but a habit.”[11]

When it comes to the Intellectual Virtues there is no doctrine of the mean, the more intelligent you are the better. Aristotle lists the following as Intellectual Virtues:

  • Technical skill – e.g. knowing how to build a house.
  • Scientific knowledge – knowing facts about biology, geography, etc.
  • Prudence – knowing how to balance your needs with those of others.
  • Intelligence – mathematical abilities and the like.
  • Wisdom – this is gained through long years of experience and helps you to make judgements about what to do.
  • Resourcefulness – knowing how and where to get the best information from.
  • Understanding – this goes beyond knowing facts, but sees the whole issue and all the complex difficulties associated with decision making.
  • Judgement – for a judgement to be good it has to take in to account what is right and good for all concerned.
  • Cleverness – this is important as it helps you to work out how to get what you want, but on its own without good judgement it can be unscrupulous, for example many criminals are very clever in their machinations.  
Of course, a major objection is that this does not seem like a moral theory at all, because seemingly a very evil person can function well, and all of these Virtues can be abused – intelligence and courage can be used by people to carry out acts of theft, rape, and genocide.  This was the criticism given by Immanuel Kant, who therefore came to the conclusion that the only thing which can be called good without qualification is a good will.  To counter this, Aristotle would argue that as a social animal we have duties to society and that because actions such as theft and killing are destructive to social harmony it follows that they are immoral, and the Intellectual Virtues would allow an individual to realise this.  However, egoist philosophers like Thomas Hobbes would argue that knowledge, cleverness, and all of the other virtues exist simply to allow the individual to get what they personally desire without concern for the impact on others.


Man as a Naturally Political Animal
Aristotle classifies man as a ‘zoon politikon’, that is, a political animal, and his classification of man as such is of central importance to Aristotle’s political theories about how societies should function. In the Greece of Aristotle’s times nations were small, generally consisting of a polis (city-state) and the countryside around it. Aristotle took the view that human beings are naturally social beings which means that we are not true individuals but are actually by nature members of a society, be it a country, a city, or just a clan. Without society you are incomplete because without other people it would be impossible for you to survive or develop your potential and achieve any kind of good life for yourself. A society is in many senses like a huge family or club that nurtures and protects its members, and without the group the individual is nothing, as Aristotle puts it in his Politics, a human being who is not part of a society is either a god or an animal – either he is magnificent and self-sufficient, or he is lacking in humanity and reason, things which are only possible through being raised in a society. All of this entails certain duties to society and that you should often put the needs of your community before your own needs, as Aristotle himself puts it “man is born for citizenship.”[12]

Today this view is known as Communitarianism or Collectivism and it is the sentiment that lies behind John Donne’s famous assertion “no man is an island entire of itself.”[13]  Donne also uses an analogy with a book; each of us is a page but a page by itself makes no sense without the whole. Modern Communitarians such as FH Bradley would argue that your society is not some alien entity outside of you, but it is actually part of your very own identity, your society is part of what you are, and therefore that you should help others, serve your society, and celebrate its culture and traditions. There is, of course, the possibility of taking this position to the extreme and concluding that individuals ought to be totally subservient to society just as bees are to their hive and ants are to their colony; this can lead us to totalitarianism all too easily.

In contrast to Communitarianism there is Atomism according to which each person is an individual, complete in his own right and master of his own self. From an Atomist perspective the individual is primary in importance and society or the state is seen as an imposition on the individual’s natural freedom; moreover there are no natural duties to other people. This view is perhaps best summed up in Margaret Thatcher’s famous aphorism “There is no such thing as society. There are individual men and women, and there are families.”[14] This was the view taken by Social Contract philosophers such as Hobbes who imagined man in his natural state as an individual who could do whatever he desired whenever he desired without any concern for others. Hobbes believed that having to live with others, help them, take their needs in to consideration, and do what you are told to by rulers, was unnatural and that societies could only exercise authority over an individual if he had personally agreed to be a member of that society and abide by its rules via a social contract. This can also be seen as morally problematic as it seems to encourage selfishness and indifference towards the needs of others.

In Aristotle’s own time there were philosophers such as Lycophron who took an Atomist point of view and therefore argued that people should be selfish if they could get away with it, and that the government of the polis had no right to order people what to do.  Aristotle wanted to show that this was not the case: society is natural and has existed as long as human beings have existed, we are citizens by nature, part of a greater whole that we must recognise is greater than us. Therefore in Aristotle’s view society has a natural right to control its members and impose laws on them, and we individuals have obligations to our communities.


Aristotle’s classification of man as a ‘political animal’
In The History of Animals, one of his biological treatises, Aristotle sets down the following classification of mankind as political animals. Firstly, Aristotle defines man as an animal, although it is important to note that man alone amongst the animals has ‘logos’ (speech, reason, or thought) which elevates us above the beasts.

Animals can be gregarious or solitary; human beings are gregarious;
Gregarious animals can be political or non-political; human beings are political;
Political animals can be leader-led or anarchic; human beings are leader-led.

Gregarious animals are those who live in herds or communities of some form (i.e. social animals) and solitary animals are those who do not. Tigers are solitary, with males and females only interacting for reproduction, and mothers only staying with their children until they are old enough to fend for themselves. Meanwhile, animals like cattle, lions, and rabbits exist in groups, as do primates; these animals are social.

Among the social animals we find those who are non-political and live for their own ends, and those who are what Aristotle describes as ‘political.’ Political animals are those who work together for a single aim. Cows mill around together and eat grass, but they do not work together to achieve goals.  Meanwhile, creatures such as ants work together to build nests, protect the colony, and forage for food.

Amongst the political animals we have those who do as they wish as individuals and so are anarchical, and those who act under the instruction of commanders. Ants are directed by a queen, but something like a colony of penguins has no leader; penguins huddle together for warmth and those on the outside will freeze if they stay there long enough, which will eventually lead to the deaths of all, so everyone takes a turn, they all shuffle round. There is no leader that organises them, they just get it done, so this may be described as anarchical.

Aristotle sees mankind as leader led, political, gregarious animals.  But was he right to do so?  It takes no genius to see that this is the way humans are currently arranged, but there is a difference between how things are and how they ought to be, or how they are naturally.  According to Hobbes society and social living are not natural, it is natural for us to be individuals and society is a synthetic creation, something we have chosen to form for the sake of self-preservation.  Meanwhile, to Aristotle a man who lives outside of a society is like a fish out of water and anyone who lives outside of a society must be either a god or an animal.


The household, village, and city-state (polis)
In order to defend his view that mankind naturally lives in societies Aristotle looks at our most basic needs and drives and states that these can only be satisfied by living with others, and therefore that living in communities is natural, it is the way we are meant to live:

In the first place there must be a union of those who cannot exist without each other; namely, of male and female, that the race may continue (and this is a union which is formed, not of deliberate purpose, but because, in common with other animals and with plants, mankind have a natural desire to leave behind them an image of themselves), and of natural ruler and subject, that both may be preserved.[15] [note: many translations use ‘master and slave’]  Aristotle, Politics

Aristotle begins his analysis of the polis (city-state) by breaking it down into what he perceives as its smallest constituent parts and justifying the existence of these. He argues that the most basic constituent of the polis is the household (oikia). The household is constituted by persons who share two relations; that between a man and woman who come together to procreate (which gives us the further relationship of parent and child); and that between a master and his slaves whereby they cater for his daily needs, such as food, shelter, and warmth. These are our most basic needs and they can only even begin to be satisfied by living with other people in small communities. Remember that no one is born a self-sufficient adult, it takes years to raise children, so we are all naturally members of at least one small community, a household or family.

Many people would agree that the needs for material provisions and procreation do indeed mean that it is natural to live in groups in this way, however, what people often find problematic is the idea of a natural relationship between master and slave.  Aristotle’s Politics gives an argument in favour of slavery, and he himself actually owned slaves. Aristotle rejects equality and takes the view that some people are better than others and are worth more; those who are capable of virtue, civil duty, and philosophical knowledge, are better quality human beings than those who are not, and therefore they have the right to rule over and direct those beneath them in precisely the same way that the human race rules over animals. Many modern philosophers find this morally repugnant, and others try to excuse it by saying that Aristotle was a product of his times and culture, like all of us; they also point out that Greek slavery was far more liberal than that of later times and slaves were generally well treated. 

Some philosophers argue that we can reinterpret Aristotle in a more acceptable light and see him as simply pointing out the distinction between bosses and employees which is common to most human endeavours: there are architects and then there are builders; there are doctors and then there are nurses to assist them; there is the engineer who designs a new car, and then there are the machinists who build the parts and assemble it. Satisfying material needs requires teamwork, but we all have different talents; where one person has the brains to design a cathedral others without those brains will have the physical ability to build it. Perhaps we might like to say that all human beings have equal dignity, but we cannot in truth claim that all human beings are equally skilled and useful. Human endeavours require leadership, and necessarily include relationships of subordination with one person directing the efforts of others. There is evidence for this more liberal interpretation of Aristotle in his text, because Aristotle specifically said that the relationship between master and slave existed for mutual benefit, and that where there was no mutual benefit then slavery was not justified:

That which can foresee by the exercise of mind is by nature intended to be lord and master, and that which can with its body give effect to such foresight is a subject, and by nature a slave; hence master and slave have the same interest...[16] where the relation of master and slave between them is natural they are friends and have a common interest, but where it rests merely on law and force the reverse is true.[17] 
Aristotle, Politics

Aristotle added that the slave of the poor man was an ox, and also that if machines could operate themselves there would be little need for slaves. Essentially Aristotle saw large amounts of humanity as being like children who needed direction from those with more intelligence, something which may have seemed true in a time when most people were not educated. If we can reinterpret Aristotle in this ‘teamwork is required but teams require leaders’ manner then the idea of living and working together and having leaders being natural becomes far more palatable and easy to agree with.

Aristotle continues by stating that the need for self-sufficiency leads to the village, that is, a collection of households, often originally constituted from extended families (grandparents, children, grandchildren etc). By forming in to small communities we can protect ourselves better and be more productive. Think of the difference between a corner shop and a supermarket; in a corner shop there might be four or five employees each fulfilling many tasks, but in a supermarket there are many workers, each of which can focus on one task, which they can specialise in and get better at, which is more efficient and productive. All supermarket chains started out as individual stores, and it can be said that the large store is just a natural expansion of the small store. So it is with the household and the village or town, and just like a household, a village will require some form of leadership.

Finally we have the polis which is a set of villages united as a city-state; a complete entity with self-sufficiency that caters for all a man’s needs, a place where our basic needs can be fulfilled, and also where eudaimonia is fully possible:

When several villages are united in a single complete community, large enough to be nearly or quite self-sufficing, the state comes into existence, originating in the bare needs of life, and continuing in existence for the sake of a good life. And therefore, if the earlier forms of society are natural, so is the state, for it is the end of them, and the nature of a thing is its end. For what each thing is when fully developed, we call its nature, whether we are speaking of a man, a horse, or a family. Besides, the final cause and end of a thing is the best, and to be self-sufficing is the end and the best. Hence it is evident that the state is a creation of nature, and that man is by nature a political animal.                Aristotle, Politics [18]    

Bringing Aristotle’s teleological perspective in to the equation, Aristotle would argue that just as it is the goal and purpose of an acorn to become an oak tree, so too is it the purpose of a household to become a village and for a village to develop in to a nation, and for him this makes it right and good to live in societies. Not only this, but it is through the existence of the state that human beings are able to grow and develop as nature intended. Living in a fully developed civil society allows our nascent potential to be brought to life; human beings have a need for art, virtue, and knowledge, and it is only in the polis that these can flourish. Large societies such as city states or countries are therefore our natural home, not a synthetic creation; human beings need society and cannot have good lives without it. For Aristotle the government is not some alien agency interfering unjustly with your life, it is a collection of the best and wisest people in society who have got together to help make life better for us all by making sure we are safe, that we have access to necessities, and that it is possible for people to actualise their potential and flourish. Of course, Aristotle was an elitist and for him it was only the rich aristocratic elite who were capable of achieving eudaimonia, but modern philosophers such as Richard Norman argue that we should try to reinterpret his philosophy as an encouragement to help all human beings actualise their personal potential via education.[19] For Aristotle, living with others in a society is natural and this requires laws and that we take others in to account with our actions.  Living with others in a society requires the existence of a government that we are obliged to obey because the leadership of the government is just a natural progression on the leadership of a man over his household, as stated above, “if the earlier forms of society are natural, so is the state”[20] and therefore we are social animals by nature: “man is born for citizenship.”[21]


Language and the social nature of mankind
For Aristotle what is natural is therefore right and good. Many people would disagree with this and argue, for example, that violence and greed are natural in human beings but that this does not make them good things, instead they ought to be fought against and controlled.  None the less, Aristotle provides three further arguments to the effect that it is natural for us to live in societies.

Firstly, Aristotle points out that most of us crave the company of others, stating in his Nicomachean Ethics that nobody would choose to live without friends even if he had all the other good things in life. Strictly speaking this is not true as some people have chosen riches above friendship, but it is also certain that many would not; if we were not social animals then it seems odd that so many of us should crave human contact.

Secondly, when Aristotle states that those who live outside of society are animals it may be interpreted to mean that without socialisation and interaction with other people we would lack humanity, after all, Aristotle believes that virtue is only possible in society. In modern times there have been numerous instances of so called ‘feral children’ who, like Mowgli or Tarzan, have grown up outside of human society and instead in association with animals. In many cases these children act like animals, for example walking on all fours, eating raw meat, and biting other people. Most show no interest in sex or money, and most show no ability to learn language or moral rules, especially when they are older. Some have even been unable to recognise their own reflections in a mirror.[22] What this seems to suggest is that being nurtured by a human community is thoroughly necessary to make us in to the adults we become, we need socialisation to unlock or develop various aspects of our humanity, and therefore that we are little or nothing without our society. Remember that we are not born as self-conscious and independent adults, we must first go through many years of being cared for by others.

The third argument is from speech.  If we are not meant to live together, why are we so highly capable of conversation?  Why not just growl to make our presence known as many other animals do?  Aristotle argues that nature provides each species with what they need to survive and achieve their best possible lives, and so since we have speech it is a good indication that we are meant to speak and converse with each other, that we are meant to learn from each other, and that we are meant to cooperate.  This argument is flawed because it once again depends on the teleological notion that nature has designed us with some kind of purpose in mind, but a similar argument can be constructed through looking at evolutionary biology. Human beings are capable of language because of our highly developed brains and vocal chords; these are things which have evolved over time due to necessities and our situation.  Human brains are more complicated versions of the simpler brains possessed by primate species, the main difference being the possession of the neo-cortex which extends our ability to reason, remember things, and learn and predict behaviours. In large colonies of primates we find a greater degree of social interaction, and what scientists find is that these primates have larger brains, greater use of tools, better problem solving abilities, better memories, and more complex language forms than those in small colonies. The conclusion seems to be that social interaction is responsible for the evolution of language and intelligence because these are necessary for social creatures to interact and succeed in the competition for food, power, and mates. Human beings are only so smart and linguistically talented as we are because our ancestors lived in social groups, so it seems that in evolutionary terms we were social even before we became human, and that we only have the physical and mental nature that we do because of our sociability, hence, we are social by nature.


An analysis of Aristotle’s views on human nature
These criticisms have been mentioned or hinted at above, this is merely a summary.


1) Aristotle relies too heavily on teleology
Aristotle took it for granted that the world has inbuilt purposes which have been established somehow by nature or perhaps by God: he believed that there are things that we exist in order to do and achieve. He used phrases such as “nature makes nothing in vain” which present us with the view that nature has designed things with a particular role in mind, which these things then ought to achieve. But this view is rejected by our modern scientific paradigm of cause and effect in the universe, a chain of events which is cold, indifferent, and thoroughly unplanned. For example, it is not the case that the sun has been put there by nature to provide us with life, the sun just happens by chance to be there and to provide the conditions for life to emerge. Aristotle utilises his teleological perspective to justify normative conclusions about how human beings ought to live, what they should try to achieve, and so on, but if we reject his teleology then these conclusions seem to lose their force. Instead of saying that humans ought to live in societies and obey their leaders we can only say that most humans happen to live in societies. If we reject Aristotle’s teleology it becomes impossible to say that the purpose of our lives is to gain knowledge or serve society, all we can say is that these are things that some people wish to do. Without Aristotle’s teleological notions we cannot make any conclusions as to the purpose of life, nor can we say that a life of knowledge is better than a life of pleasure, or that a life of social duty is better than a solitary or self-serving existence.


2) Aristotle’s description of the human mind or psyche is too simplistic
The nature of the human mind is an important part of the debate about what human beings are and Aristotle gives an interesting perspective on this issue: the mind is the functions that are being carried out by the body, like nutrition, respiration, perception, emotions, and reasoning; there is no eternal soul, when we die these functions stop and the mind no longer exists. Aristotle’s analysis has some similarities with modern scientific theories, for example, the Vegetative Soul seems to bear a large similarity to the idea of there being certain hallmarks of life such as respiration, excretion, and growth. However, it could be said that the processes that are going on within the variety of living beings in the world are far more varied and complex than Aristotle realises. For example, Aristotle draws a clear line between human beings and animals saying that only humans can reason and animals do not, but it seems clear from studying animals that many other animals have basic languages and the ability to reason in order to select the best course of action for their goals.

Aristotle reaches normative conclusions based on his psychological treatise, for he believes that since only humans can reason this means that it is our special purpose in life to reason and gain knowledge, and that this is more important than lower things such as pleasure or even personal survival. However, if animals can reason too then this does not seem to be a special purpose for us anymore, it is not a distinctive feature of humanity.  Also, why not take the view that reason exists simply to help us have more success in achieving survival and pleasure? Why assume that reasoning and knowledge are the end rather than the means?  According to Hobbes reason and knowledge exist to serve the body’s survival, whereas Aristotle seems to say that the body is there in order to allow us to reason and have knowledge. From an evolutionary perspective where we are taking in to account notions of ‘survival of the fittest’ it seems that Hobbes is closer to the truth than Aristotle.


3) Aristotle says very little about the character of man
Aristotle says a lot about how a human being should be, but not much about what we are actually like, for example, Hobbes says that all human beings are selfish and inclined to use violence and manipulation to get what they want, but we do not seem to get blanket statements like this from Aristotle. On the other hand, perhaps this is a strength, for it seems that Aristotle is aware of the fact that different people act in different ways.  If we look at the table of virtues and vices we can see that there is a broad range of different ways people can act, and surely we would be able to point out people who act in all of these ways. Some people are mean and do not share their wealth with others, whilst others are generous, and some are too generous giving away more than they can sensibly afford, or are wasteful. There seems to be a recognition in Aristotle’s writing that people act in different ways, and that they have different jobs to do in life. What he is saying is that there are certain character traits that it would benefit everyone to develop; what Aristotle gives us is not a description of what people are actually like, but rather, a picture of what they ought to be in order to have what he sees as a happy and successful life.


4) Problems with Aristotle’s notions of happiness
Aristotle takes it for granted that all of us want to be happy and he takes the view that every action we perform aims at attaining happiness. He then describes three different points of view on what it means to be happy: to have pleasure; to have knowledge; to have friends or serve the community and have the respect of others. He rules out a life of pleasure as being the kind of life that only an animal desires, and belittles those who desire such a life. He then lays down rules for how to achieve knowledge and perform social duties well. In many ways this is a good approach as he is saying “people want happiness, this is how to get it.” However, it might be argued that happiness is not really the only thing we aim at, for example some people seem to go out of their way to make their own lives miserable, or they lack the motivation to make simple changes that would benefit their lives. Moreover, it could be said that happiness is a very vague concept because we are all made happy by different things; for some happiness comes from helping others, whereas for others it comes from hurting or bullying people. For some happiness comes from fitness and exercise, whilst for others it comes from being a couch potato, so how can Aristotle really say that happiness consists only in a particular lifestyle, a lifestyle which happens to be his own?  Moreover, is Aristotle really correct to rule out a life of pleasure as the goal that we should all seek? After all, surely the reason why he himself was a philosopher was because he enjoyed the hunt for knowledge? According to Jeremy Bentham all pleasures are of equal worth and a simple game such as push-pin is just as good as poetry. On the other hand, neo-Aristotelians such as Rosalind Hursthouse would say that the beauty of Aristotle’s point of view is that it says there is more to life than material wealth and hedonism; a truly good life can be lived through having friends and family, helping others, and trying to be a decent and benevolent human being who is respected by other people for their many good qualities.[23]


5) Criticisms of Aristotle’s theory of virtues
Immanuel Kant believed that virtue theories were incomplete as moral theories because all of the different virtues could be abused, for example, intelligence can be used to plan robberies and courage can be used to go out and do them. For Kant what was required was a set of rules and a willingness to follow those rules, but Aristotle’s virtue ethics does not provide us with rules to live by.  Suppose that a teenage girl finds herself pregnant and is considering an abortion; telling her to do the courageous thing doesn’t really help, what is more courageous, facing the difficulties of motherhood or facing the difficulties of terminating the pregnancy?  However, Aristotle believes that these rules can largely be filled in by nature or society; firstly, in order for any society to function at all certain rules have to be followed such as having restrictions on stealing, violence, and killing; secondly, in order to get on well with our peers traits such as honesty and helpfulness are required so it becomes morally correct to tell the truth and help others where we can; thirdly, nature can suggest various moral truths, for example, that wives should not be treated like slaves because they are capable of reasoning and knowledge just as men are (although Aristotle by no means believed in gender equality); lastly, Aristotle accepts Cultural Relativism and believed that in general you should follow local moral customs and traditions. Some find this problematic as they believe that the practices of many cultures are morally repugnant and that these should be a universal code of right and wrong meaning that things such as torture or honour killings should not happen anywhere, but for Aristotle Cultural Relativism was a fact of life clear to plain observation of other cultures.


6) Aristotle’s elitism and advocation of slavery
Another criticism is that Aristotle is an elitist and that the virtues he highlights are those which were needed to be a successful Greek noble in his own times, for example, by declaring intelligence and generosity with money are virtues he automatically precludes those who are poor or less intelligent from being virtuous.  On the other hand it could be argued that all people are capable of developing a broad range of the virtues to one degree or another, even if they cannot have all of the virtues, for example a person may be poor but they can still be generous by spending their time to help others, and everyone could benefit from temperance.

However, what is more troublesome is Aristotle’s view that because of their lack of virtues and intelligence some people are low quality human beings whose lives are less important and valuable. He takes the view that some people are so lacking in intelligence and virtue that they are little better than animals, and therefore are naturally suited to slavery. To modern moral perspectives this is an unacceptable view, however, Aristotle himself did state that slavery would be unnecessary if machines could operate themselves and this is now indeed the case. Additionally, he thought of slavery as being something for the mutual benefit of both slave and master: some people are incapable of governing themselves and so that they need to be ruled by others, for their own benefit and survival. What we must remember is that in Aristotle’s times very few people were educated, so this may have seemed true, but thanks to universal education in the West we can see that all or most people are capable of becoming rational self-governing agents. Perhaps then, we should take Aristotle’s notions of eudaimonia as an inspiration to create a society where as many people as possible can achieve good lives with knowledge and virtue, that we should recognise our shared humanity and try to bring the best out in people?  Where Aristotle does seem to have a good point is in the notion that working relationships require some people to be higher than others, and we should be stationed according to our abilities, like the relationship between an architect and his builders.  However, according to philosophers such as Friedrich Nietzsche, Aristotle was exactly right to reject equality, some people are just better, more useful, and more valuable and important than others and we should just accept this and reject the myth that we all have equal worth.


7) Man is not a completely social animal
Aristotle gives compelling evidence that it is natural for us to live in communities of some form, after all, without communal living infants would never be able to become sentient and intelligent adults, and without communal living language would not exist at all. Modern evolutionary evidence of which Aristotle had no knowledge appears to support Aristotle’s view in this matter. Aristotle is also correct to suggest that our basic needs can only be fully met within a community, however, is it not too simple to just classify man is a social animal?  Human beings are not like ants whose entire existence appears to be a blind subservience to the colony, and very few of us would wish to live this way, we often strive for our personal freedom and autonomy. Is it not more realistic to say that human beings have a mixed nature, being part social, part individual? 

From an early age we depend on other people such as our parents, and we pick up their opinions and habits, but at the same time we always have our own minds and ideas.  In various cases we find that we cannot be happy without others, but at the same time we often find that “hell is other people”[24] to quote Jean-Paul Sartre.  Each of us seems to be a mixture of the social and the individual, so that neither view is completely correct, and some people are more social than others whilst others are more independent than others. Moreover, it appears that as we grow up and mature we often become increasingly independent; perhaps we are social animals as children, but in time many of us become the kind of independent individuals that Atomists such as Hobbes took all mankind to be? 

Aristotle used his thesis that we are social and political animals to argue for the idea that we should serve society and follow the commands of its governors, but taken to its extreme this would lead to a totalitarian state such as Stalin’s Russia, Hitler’s Germany, or some kind of autocracy like a Medieval feudal system.  Since few of us would find this an ideal situation to live in it follows that we are not entirely social beings, but equally, we might want to argue that the opposite situation where there is no community spirit of sense of obligation to others is equally troubling to us, and that we need others, in which case we are not wholly individuals either. This line of reasoning seems to suggest that neither Aristotle’s Communitarianism nor Hobbes’ Atomism provides the full truth as human beings are a mixture of the social and the individual.


Conclusion
Aristotle provides us with vivid ideas about what the human soul or psyche consists in, and presents an excellent case for the notion that human beings are social beings. However, he seems to overstate his case because human beings appear to be part social, part individual. Aristotle also provides us with challenging ideas about what makes a good and meaningful human life and what kind of person we should attempt to be.  Though many objections can be directed towards his views he does indeed provide us with a remarkable picture of what human beings can become and achieve.  Perhaps what is most difficult in Aristotle is his rejection of equality, however we must not presume that Aristotle is wrong, for if we wish to argue that all human beings are equal in worth and dignity despite their many differences in talent and ability we will need to provide strong reasons for why this is so.


Suggested Further Reading:
Aristotle, Ethics, books 1 and 2.
Aristotle, Politics, book 1.
Jonathan Barnes, Aristotle: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press (2000).
Richard Kraut, Aristotle’s Ethics, presented in The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy: http://www.seop.leeds.ac.uk/entries/aristotle-ethics/ (accessed on 12/08/11).
Wolfgang Kullmann, Man as a Political Animal in Aristotle, presented in David Keyt and Fred Miller (eds.), A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, Blackwell Publishers (1991).
Richard Norman, The Moral Philosophers: An Introduction To Ethics, OUP (1998).


Bibliography / References



[1] Aristotle, De Anima (On The Soul), translated by JA Smith, Book II, part 1, available online at: http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/soul.1.i.html (accessed 25/05/11).
[2] Aristotle, De Anima (On The Soul), Book II, part 2.
[3] Aristotle, De Anima (On The Soul), Book II, part 2.
[4] Aristotle, De Anima (On The Soul), Book III, part 3.
[5] Aristotle, Politics, translated by Benjemin Jowett, Book I, part 2, available online at: http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/politics.1.one.html (accessed 04/05/11).
[6] Aristotle, De Anima (On The Soul), Book III, part 9.
[7]  Aristotle, Politics, Book I, part 2.
[8]   Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, Book I, part 4.
[9]  Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, Book I, part 5.
[10]  JS Mill, Utilitarianism. Chapter 2.
[11]  Will Durrant, The Story of Philosophy: The Lives and Opinions of the World's Greatest Philosophers (1926).
[12]  Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, translated by WD Ross, Book 1, Chapter 7.
[13]  John Donne, Devotions Upon Emergent Occasions, Meditation XVII.
[14]  Margaret Thatcher, available at: http://www.theanswerbank.co.uk/Phrases-and-Sayings/Question164326.html (accessed 21/05/11).
[15] Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, part 2.
[16] Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, part 2.
[17] Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, part 6.
[18]  Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, part 2.
[19]  cf. Richard Norman, The Moral Philosophers: An Introduction To Ethics, Oxford University Press (1998).
[20]  Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, part 2.
[21]  Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, translated by WD Ross, Book 1, Chapter 7.
[22]  Source: unnamed author, Feral Children, http://www.bbc.co.uk/dna/h2g2/alabaster/A269840/ (accessed 11/08/11).
[23] cf. Rosalind Hursthouse, Beginning Lives, Blackwell Publishers (1987), pp. 218-37.
[24] Jean-Paul Sartre, No Exit.

No comments:

Post a Comment